Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Law, Business and Innovation ((PLBI))

  • 779 Accesses

Abstract

After the previous considerations based on the economic analysis of law, the backbone of the theoretical framework of this work is substantiated in the theory submitted by Scott Shapiro in his book Legality (2011) where he adopts Michael Bratman ’s suggestion that we are all “planning agents .”

We are all planning creatures” (Bratman 2001, p. 203).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 120).

  2. 2.

    Lessig (1998, pp. 661–691).

  3. 3.

    Michael Bratman is a Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Stanford University. His work focuses on moral philosophy and the philosophy of action including many issues related to human agency and practical reason.

  4. 4.

    Bratman (1984, pp. 375–405).

  5. 5.

    See Audi (1973, pp. 387-403), Beardsley (1978), Churchland (1970, pp. 214–236).

  6. 6.

    Bratman (1984, pp. 375–376).

  7. 7.

    Bratman (1984, pp. 379–380).

  8. 8.

    Velleman (1991, p. 277).

  9. 9.

    Bratman (1999, pp. 1–2).

  10. 10.

    Bratman (1999, pp. 2–3).

  11. 11.

    Canale (2013, p. 19).

  12. 12.

    Alonso (2008, p. 78).

  13. 13.

    Bratman (1999, p. 3).

  14. 14.

    O’Hagan (2001, p. 393).

  15. 15.

    Bratman (1999, p. 3).

  16. 16.

    Mohan (1990, p. 89).

  17. 17.

    See Fischer (2005, p. 217) (ed).

  18. 18.

    Mohan (1990, pp. 89–90).

  19. 19.

    Bratman (1999, p. 3).

  20. 20.

    O’Hagan (2001, p. 393).

  21. 21.

    Tuomela (2014).

  22. 22.

    Bratman (2014a).

  23. 23.

    Bratman (2014a), Westerlund (2015, pp. 822–836).

  24. 24.

    Bratman (2013, 2014b).

  25. 25.

    Bratman (1992, pp. 327–331).

  26. 26.

    See, generally, Searle (1983, 1995).

  27. 27.

    See, generally, Gilbert (2006).

  28. 28.

    Searle (2010, pp. 46–47), Searle (1990, pp. 401–416).

  29. 29.

    Bratman (2013, 2014b).

  30. 30.

    Bratman (2013, 2014a, b).

  31. 31.

    Gilbert (1990, pp. 1–14).

  32. 32.

    If you fail to give me what I have a right to through your promise, I have the standing, as your promise, to rebuke you on that account. Similarly, should you threaten to break your promise, I have the standing, as your promise, to command or insist that you act as promised, and thus pressure you to perform.” The work of Margaret Gilbert , see Owens (2012, p. 50).

  33. 33.

    Gilbert (2007, pp. 31–49), Gilbert (2000), But see Sheeney (2002, pp. 377–394).

  34. 34.

    Gilbert (2007, pp. 31–49).

  35. 35.

    Bratman (2013, 2014b).

  36. 36.

    Bratman (2013, 2014b).

  37. 37.

    See, generally, Wend (1975) (ed).

  38. 38.

    Bratman (2014a, pp. 10–11).

  39. 39.

    Bratman (2014a, p. 11).

  40. 40.

    Bratman (2014a, p. 15).

  41. 41.

    Bratman (2013, 2014a).

  42. 42.

    Bratman (2013, 2014b).

  43. 43.

    Bratman (2013, 2014b).

  44. 44.

    Bratman (2013, 2014b).

  45. 45.

    According to Bratman: “The limitation is that my focus will be primarily on the shared intentional activities of small, adult groups in the absence of asymmetric authority relations within those groups, and in which the individuals who are participants remain constant over time.” See Bratman (2014a, p. 7).

  46. 46.

    Bratman (2014a, p. 8).

  47. 47.

    See, generally, Coleman (1998).

  48. 48.

    Coleman (1988, 1998, pp. 95–120).

  49. 49.

    See, generally, Hart (1997).

  50. 50.

    See, generally, Dworkin (1986).

  51. 51.

    See, generally, Austin (1832, 1869).

  52. 52.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 12–13).

  53. 53.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 118 et seq).

  54. 54.

    Stone (2011, p. 7). Stone actually believes that Plan Theory does not pertain only to the field of analytical legal positivism , but rather extends and even thrives in the context of natural law. For a full recount of positivism and the separation of law and morals, see Hart (1958, pp. 593–629).

  55. 55.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 195).

  56. 56.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 205, 179 et seq).

  57. 57.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 168).

  58. 58.

    See, generally, Canale (2013, pp. 1–126).

  59. 59.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 309).

  60. 60.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 124, 140).

  61. 61.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 139, 200, 275).

  62. 62.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 170–173, 213–214, 217, 309, 312, 337–339, 348).

  63. 63.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 134).

  64. 64.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 118 et seq).

  65. 65.

    Pino (2013, pp. 187–188).

  66. 66.

    Ferrer Beltran and Ratti (2013, p. 182).

  67. 67.

    See, generally, Easterbrook (1994, pp. 61–70).

  68. 68.

    See, generally, Murray, Methods of Interpretation: Comparative Law Method, Report of Mr. Justice John Murray, President of the Supreme Court and Chief Justice of Ireland, Actes du colloque pour le cinquantiéme anniversaire des Traité de Rome, pp. 39–47.

  69. 69.

    Pino (2013), Chap. 9 with further references.

  70. 70.

    Pino (2013), Chap. 9 with further references, Shapiro (2011, pp. 335 et seq).

  71. 71.

    Dworkin (1986, p. 380).

  72. 72.

    Dworkin (1986, p. 308).

  73. 73.

    Dworkin (1982, p. 182, 1996a, pp. 29–46), Levinson and Mailloux (1991, p. 271) (eds).

  74. 74.

    Samuel (2013, p. 102).

  75. 75.

    Bontekoe (2004, p. 24).

  76. 76.

    Dworkin suggested that “judges are like authors jointly creating a chain novel in which each writes a chapter that makes sense as part of the story as a whole.” For an in-depth rundown see Dworkin (1996b, p. 10). For a better treatment see also Wacks (2015, p. 147, 2014, p. 59), Culver (1999, p. 183) (ed), Samuel (2014, p. 183), Berns (1993, p. 149), Darian-Smith (2013, pp. 136–137).

  77. 77.

    Dworkin (1975, pp. 1057–1109).

  78. 78.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 307).

  79. 79.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 307).

  80. 80.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 278).

  81. 81.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 282–307).

  82. 82.

    Shapiro (2011, pp. 282–307).

  83. 83.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 310).

  84. 84.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 348).

  85. 85.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 348).

  86. 86.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 311).

  87. 87.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 311).

  88. 88.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 311).

  89. 89.

    See, generally, Raz (1999).

  90. 90.

    See, generally, Shiner (2005, p. 57).

  91. 91.

    Pino (2013, p. 191).

  92. 92.

    Pino (2013, p. 134).

  93. 93.

    Pino (2013, p. 139).

  94. 94.

    Howells (2006, pp. 715–728).

  95. 95.

    Stewart and Hyysalo (2008, pp. 295–325).

  96. 96.

    Hallersted (2013, p. 35).

  97. 97.

    Osorio et al. (2012, p. 201), Antikainen (2011, p. 189).

  98. 98.

    Nauwelaers (2011, p. 474).

  99. 99.

    Hallersted (2013, p. 35).

  100. 100.

    Hallersted (2013, p. 36).

  101. 101.

    Agogue et al. (2012, pp. 1–31).

  102. 102.

    Hallersted (2013, pp. 36–37).

  103. 103.

    Dalziel and Parjanen (2012, p. 120).

  104. 104.

    See Stewart and Hyysalo (2008, pp. 295–325).

  105. 105.

    I will expound these thoughts in Chap. 7, which focuses on Behavioral Law and Economics and Nudge Theory .

  106. 106.

    Bridgeman (2009, p. 343).

  107. 107.

    Shapiro (2011, p. 41).

  108. 108.

    Lessig (2006, pp. 120–137), Appendix, pp. 340–345.

  109. 109.

    Lessig (2004, pp. 121–173).

  110. 110.

    Lessig (2006, p. 123).

  111. 111.

    Lessig (2006, pp. 314–340).

  112. 112.

    Lessig (2004, p. 122).

  113. 113.

    Lessig (2006, p. 341).

  114. 114.

    Boudriga (2009, pp. 21–23); see also, generally, Zwicky et al. (2000).

  115. 115.

    Lessig (2004, pp. 112–123).

  116. 116.

    Lessig (2006, p. 81).

  117. 117.

    Lessig (2006, p. 81).

  118. 118.

    Lessig (2006, pp. 342–343), see also, generally, Reidenberg (1998, pp. 553–593).

  119. 119.

    Lessig (2002, p. 121), Lessig (1999, pp. 501–546).

  120. 120.

    See Hustinx (2010, pp. 253–255), Cavoukian (2012).

  121. 121.

    Bianco et al. (2008, p. 8).

  122. 122.

    Sharaf and Djemame (2015, pp. 177–191).

  123. 123.

    Schote (2012, p. 63).

  124. 124.

    Sharaf and Djemame (2015, pp. 177–191).

  125. 125.

    Bridgeman (2009, pp. 341–342).

  126. 126.

    Bridgeman (2009, p. 343).

  127. 127.

    Bridgeman (2009, p. 344).

  128. 128.

    Bridgeman (2009, p. 344).

  129. 129.

    Bridgeman (2009, p. 344).

  130. 130.

    See Ilearian, XSD Form Features.

  131. 131.

    See, generally, Corvelle (2013) (ed), Asher (1984).

References

  • Agogue M, Ystrom A, Le Masson P (2012) Rethinking the role of intermediaries as an architect of collective exploration and creation of knowledge in open innovation. Int J Innov Manag 7(2):1–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Alonso F (2008) Shared intention, Reliance, and interpersonal obligations: an inquiry into the metaphysics and interpersonal normativity of shared agency. A Dissertation submitted to the Department of Philosophy and the committee on graduate studies of Stanford University in Partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ProQuest LLC, Ann Arbor, p 78

    Google Scholar 

  • Antikainen M (2011) Towards collaborative open innovation communities. In: Chauvel D (ed) Leading issues in innovation research, vol 1. Academic Publishing International Ltd., Reading, p 189

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi R (1973) Intending. J Philos 70:387–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin J (1832) The province of jurisprudence determined. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin J (1869) Lectures on jurisprudence on the philosophy of positive law, 3rd edn. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Beardley M (1978) Intending. In: Goldman A, Jaegwon K (eds) Values and morals: essays in honor of William Frankena, Charles Stevenson and Richard Brandt. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Berns S (1993) Concise jurisprudence. The Federation Press, Annandale, p 149

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianco P, Lewis G, Merson P (2008) Service level agreements in service-oriented architecture environments. Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, Software Engineering Institute, p 8

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bontekoe R (2004) Judicial discretion and right answers. In: Soeteman A (ed) Proceedings of the 20th IVR World Congress Pluralism and Law, Amsterdam, vol 4, Legal Reasoning. Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart (2001), p 24

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudriga N (2009) Security of mobile communications. Auerbach Publications (CRC Press), Boca Ratón, pp 21–23

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (1984) Two faces of intention. Philos Rev 93(3):375–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (1992) Shared cooperative activity. Philos Rev 101(2):327–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (1999) Intentions, plans, and practical reason, The Davis Hume Series, Philosophy and Cognitive Science Reissues. CSLI Publications, California, pp 1–2

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (2001) Taking plans seriously. In: Millgram E (ed) Varieties of practical reason. The MIT Press, Cambridge, p 203

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (2013) Shared Agency, The Science Network (TSN), Stanford University. http://thesciencenetwork.org/programs/cogsci-2013/shared-agency. Accessed 10 May 2019

  • Bratman M (2014a) Shared agency: a planning theory of acting together. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman (2014b) Acting and thinking together, Routledge Lecture in Philosophy, University of Cambridge http://upload.sms.csx.cam.ac.uk/media/1737335. Accessed 10 May 2019

  • Bridgeman C (2009) Contracts as plans. Univ Illinois Law Rev 2009(2):343

    Google Scholar 

  • Canale D (2013) Looking for the nature of law: on Shapiro’s challenge. In: Canale D, Tuzet G (eds) The planning theory of law: a critical reading, law and philosophy library, vol 100. Springer, Dordrecht, p 19

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavoukian A (2012) Operationalizing privacy by design: a guide to implementing strong privacy practices, PhD. http://www.privacybydesign.ca/content/up-loads/2013/01/operationalizing-pbd-guide.pdf. Accessed 10 May 2019

  • Churchland P (1970) The logical character of action-explanations. Philos Rev 79:214–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman J (1998) Foundations of social theory. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman J (1988) Social capital in the creation of human capital. Supplement: organizations and institutions: sociological and economic approaches to the analysis of social structure. Am J Sociol 94:95–120 The University of Chicago Press

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig J (2009) Raz and his critics: a defense of Razian authority, Master Thesis, Georgia State University. http://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/49. Accessed 10 May 2019

  • Culver K (1999) (ed) Readings in the philosophy of law. Broadview Press Ltd., Ontario, p 183

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalziel M, Parjanen S (2012) Measuring the impact of innovation intermediaries: a case study of Tekes. In: Melkas H, Harmaakorpi V (eds) Practice-based innovation: insights, applications and policy implications. Springer, Berlin, p 120

    Google Scholar 

  • Darian-Smith E (2013) Laws and societies in global contexts: contemporary approaches. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 136–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1975) Hard cases. Harv Law Rev 88(6):1057–1109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1982) Law as interpretation. Crit Inq Chic J 9(1):182

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1996a) How law is like literature. In: Ledwon L (ed) Law and literature: text and theory. Garland Publishing, New York, pp 29–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1996) Freedom’s law: the moral reading of the American Constitution, Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 10

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterbrook F (1994) Text, history, and structure in statutory interpretation. Harv J Law Public Policy 17:61–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrer Bertran J, Ratti G (2013) Theoretical disagreements: a restatement of legal positivism. In: Canale D, Tuzet G (eds) The planning theory of law: a critical reading, Law and Philosophy Library, vol 100. Springer, Dordrecht, p 182

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher J (ed) (2005) Free will: critical concepts in philosophy. Routledge, New York, p 217

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (1990) Walking together: a paradigmatic social phenomenon. Midwest Stud Philos 15(1):1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (2000) Sociality and responsibility: new essays in plural subject theory. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc., Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (2006) A theory of political obligation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (2007) Searle and collective intentions. In: Tsohatzidis S (ed) Intentional acts and institutional facts: essays on John Searle’s social ontology. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 31–49

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hallersted S (2013) Managing the lifecycle of open innovation platforms. Springer, Wiesbaden, p 35

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart H (1958) Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harv Law Rev 71(4):593–629

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart H (1997) The concept of law, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Howels J (2006) Intermediation and the role of intermediaries in innovation. Res Policy 35(5):715–728

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hustinx P (2010) Privacy by design: delivering the promises. Identity Inf Soc 3(2):253–255. Springer. http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s12394-010-0061-z. Accessed 10 May 2019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lessig L (1998) The new Chicago school. J Legal Stud 27(S2):661–691 The University of Chicago Press

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lessig L (1999) The law of the horse: what Cyberlaw might teach. Harvar Law Rev 113:501–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lessig L (2002) The future of ideas: the fate of the commons in a connected world. Vintage Books, New York, p 121

    Google Scholar 

  • Lessig L (2006) Code. Version 2.0, Appendix. Basic Books, New York, pp 120–137, pp 340–345

    Google Scholar 

  • Lessig L (2004) Free culture: the nature and future of creativity. Penguin Books, New York, pp 121–173

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson S, Mailloux S (1991) (eds) Interpreting law and literature: a hermeneutic reader. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, p 271

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohan W (1990) Intention, plans, and practical reason. Int Stud Philos 22(3):89. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Book Review)

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray J Methods of interpretation: comparative law method, Report of Mr. Justice John L. Murray, President of the Supreme Court and Chief Justice of Ireland, Actes du colloque pour le cinquantième anniversaire des Traités de Rome. http://curia.europa.eu/common/dpi/col_murray.pdf. Accessed 10 May 2019, pp 39–47

  • Nauwelaers C (2011) intermediaries in regional innovation systems: role and challenges for policy. In: Cooke P et al (eds) Handbook of regional innovation and growth. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham, p 474

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hagan E (2001) Faces of intention: selected essays on intention and agency by Michael Bratman, Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, New York (Book Review). Dialogue 40(2):393

    Google Scholar 

  • Osorio D, Jimenez M, Arroyo L (2012) Open innovation through intermediaries in the web: a comparative case study. In: de Pablos Heredero C, López D (eds) Open innovation in firms and public administrations: technologies for value creation. Information Science Reference (IGI Global), Hershey, p 201

    Google Scholar 

  • Owens D (2012) Shaping the normative landscape. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 50

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1999) Practical reason and norm. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reidenberg J (1998) Lex informatica: the formulation of information policy rules through technology. Texas Law Rev 76(3):553–593

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuel G (2013) A short introduction to the common law. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham, p 102

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuel G (2014) An introduction to comparative law: theory and method. Hart Publishing, Oxford, p 138

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1983) Intentionality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1990) Collective intentions and actions. In: Cohen P, Morgan J, Pollack M (eds) Intentions in communications. MIT Press, Cambridge. Reprinted in Searle J (2002) Consciousness and language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 401–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1995) The construction of social reality. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (2010) Making the social world: the structure of human civilization. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 46–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro S (2011) Legality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sharaf S, Djemame K (2015) Enabling service level agreement renegotiation through extending WS-agreement specification. SOCA 9(2):177–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiner R (2005) A treatise of legal philosophy and general jurisprudence: legal institutions and the sources of law, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht, p 57

    Google Scholar 

  • Schote N (2012) QoS-aware model-driven SOA using SoaML, Master Thesis, University of Twente, EEMCS–TRESE: Software Engineering Group, p 63

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart J, Hyysalo S (2008) Intermediaries, users and social learning in technological innovation. Int J Innov Manag 12(3):295–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone M (2012) Planning positivism and planning natural law. Can J Law Jurisprudence, Forthcoming; Cardozo Legal Studies Research Paper No. 363:7. http://ssrn.com/abstract=1982143. Accessed 10 May 2019

  • Tuomela R (2014) Michael E. Bratman, shared agency: a planning theory of acting together. Oxford University Press, Oxford (Book Review) https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/49830-shared-agency-a-planning-theory-of-acting-together/. Accessed 10 May 2019

  • Velleman D (1991) Intention, plans, and practical reason by Michael E. Bratman. Philos Rev 100(2):277. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (Book Review)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wacks R (2014) Philosophy of law: a very short introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 59

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wacks R (2015) Understanding jurisprudence, 4th edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 147

    Google Scholar 

  • Wend D (1975) (ed) Utility, probability and human decision making. In: Selected Proceedings of an interdisciplinary research conference, vol II, Rome, 3–6 September 1973. D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Westerlund A (2015) Shared agency: a planning theory of acting together, by Michael E, Bratman. Aust J Philos 93(2):822–836. Oxford University Press, Oxford (Book Review)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwicky E, Cooper S, Chapman D (2000) Building internet firewalls, 2nd edn. O’Reilly & Associates Inc., Sebastopol

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcelo Corrales Compagnucci .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Corrales Compagnucci, M. (2020). Plan-Like Architectures. In: Big Data, Databases and "Ownership" Rights in the Cloud. Perspectives in Law, Business and Innovation. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-0349-8_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-0349-8_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-15-0348-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-15-0349-8

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics