Skip to main content

The Qur’ānic Hints about Epistemic Responsibility: An Analysis of Etymological Variants of ‘i-l-m in the Text

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Epistemology of the Quran
  • 256 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter we examine some of the verses about perceptual, intellectual, and revelatory knowledge. It is argued that these Qur’ānic verses are best understood as ways of defining knowledge in terms of certain natural and acquired epistemic dispositions or virtues. Human beings are held accountable by the Qur’ān for the proper use of their perceptual and rational faculties. The Qur’ānic concept of revelation as God’s testimony is highlighted along with the Qur’ānic emphasis on the Prophet’s responsibility for proper communication of the content of revelation. It is argued that knowledge for the Qur’ān seems to involve effective exercise of our natural perceptual, rational, and intuitive faculties as well as acquired dispositions or intellectual virtues. The Qur’ānic verses talk both about proper use of natural faculties and exercise of acquired intellectual virtues for acquisition of knowledge. Hence, it is suggested that the divide between responsibilist and reliabilist camps of virtue epistemology needs to be bridged. Some developments in this direction are noted.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the distinction between active and passive perceptual knowledge see Pritchard (2016, 30).

  2. 2.

    This idea, along with testimonial knowledge, is used as an argument against the so-called credit view of knowledge advocated by Ernest Sosa (2007, 92 onwards), John Greco (2003, 117), and Wayne Riggs (2007, 336–41). To put it very roughly and without an eye to variations in their respective positions, these thinkers claim that knowledge is true belief attained by the epistemic agent through the exercise of her abilities/competence. Such exercise of epistemic abilities makes the agent creditworthy for attaining true belief. Zagzebsky (1996, 2009) also has a credit view of knowledge and, hence, is open to the same challenge.

  3. 3.

    The Qur’ānic term qulūb used here means heart-mind and stands for the faculty of understanding in this context. A lot of the times the Qur’ān uses the term fuād, plural afidata, to signify heart-mind which stands for consciousness as a whole including its emotive aspect.

  4. 4.

    Booth (2016, 53) notes that medieval Islamic philosophers also hold that one is responsible for the contents of her/his beliefs insofar as one has control over one’s mind to set it up to receive knowledge of first principles from the active intellect. Of course Booth’s discussion is in the context of Neo-Platonist Islamic philosophy rather than the Qur’ān which seemingly places a more direct responsibility on our shoulders for exercise of our reason.

  5. 5.

    On the question of what it means for God to speak to humans in the literal sense, there is a long tradition of theories beginning with medieval Muslim philosophers like al-Farabi and Avicenna and extending to contemporary thinkers like Fazlur Rahman (2011). Rahman’s own position can be found in the chapter on revelation in his Major Themes of the Qur’ān (2009). In a recent discussion of the matter Nicholas Wolterstorff (1995) offers a comprehensive theory on the subject couched in the language of contemporary analytic philosophy.

  6. 6.

    See Muhammad Iqbal (2012) The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam, particularly Lecture V.

  7. 7.

    Although I have not discussed memorial knowledge here, the theme of remembrance in various forms is constantly present in the Qur’ān.

  8. 8.

    As Mats Wahlberg defines it, testimonial knowledge is “knowledge gained from the spoken or written words of other people,” absent any reason for the hearer to think that the speaker is lying or misinformed (2014: 1). Most human knowledge is of this type. Only a small portion of our knowledge is acquired through personal observation or intellectual effort. The rest, even about our own biology, ancestry, community, history, and hard sciences like physics, etc., comes through the testimony of others. The true beliefs that we gain through the testimony of others, often given in books, are fully justified. Learning about some aspect of the theory of relativity, for example, through a textbook can give me justified true beliefs about relativity. In a nutshell, our lives generally depend on this kind of testimonial knowledge. Similarly, as Wahlberg argues effectively, our knowledge of God is mainly based on God’s own testimony through revelation plus our use of natural reason. We can form justified true beliefs about God on the basis of revelation. Given the fact that we broadly accept testimony as a source of knowledge in ordinary life, we need to do the same in the case of God’s testimony about His existence as well as His guidance for mankind.

  9. 9.

    Basically there are two views of testimonial knowledge in philosophical literature: reductionist and non-reductionist. Non-reductionists like J. L. Austin (1979) and many subsequent writers, claim that as long as the hearer does not have any relevant defeaters, i.e., relevant evidence to the contrary, s/he can acquire testimonial knowledge simply by the testimony of the speaker. The reductionists, among whom David Hume (1967) is the primary figure, believe that the hearer must be in possession of some independent positive reasons for accepting the testimony and only then can acquire testimonial knowledge.

  10. 10.

    Greco (2000, 182–4) argues that Zagzebsky-style intellectual virtues are neither necessary nor sufficient for knowledge and in fact we need reliabilist virtues (reliably functioning faculties) for attaining knowledge. However he seems to de-emphasize the role of acquired intellectual virtues in the acquisition of knowledge. It seems to me that in high-grade knowledge (knowledge which is the product of sustained enquiry, for example) properly functioning faculties need to be supplemented by acquired intellectual virtues. Sosa (2007, 88) also considers competences, which for him include reliable natural faculties as well as acquired virtues (2007, 86), as playing a constitutive role in attaining true beliefs that reach the status of knowledge. I take him to mean that natural faculties/virtues are presupposed by application of virtues derived from learning, i.e., acquired virtues.

  11. 11.

    That these two positions can be usefully combined comes out effectively from some recent analyses such as Juan Comesana‘s “Evidentialist Reliabilism,” where he argues that both evidentialism, an internalist position upon which responsibilism is based, and reliabilism can benefit from a combination of these two approaches in epistemology (Comesana 2010). For how evidentialism can connect with acquired intellectual virtues see Jason Baehr (2009). Alvin Goldman (2011) also proposes a synthesis of reliabilism and evidentialism. Ernest Sosa (2004) suggests in a similar vein that both internalism and externalism may be right.

References

  • Austin, J.L. 1979. Other Minds. In Philosophical Papers, ed. J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock, 3rd ed., 76–116. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, Jason. 2009. Evidentialism, Vice, and Virtue. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (3): 545–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloomfield, P. 2000. Virtue Epistemology and the Epistemology of Virtue. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 23–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Booth, A.R. 2016. Islamic Philosophy and the Ethics of Belief. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Comesana, Juan. 2010. Evidentialist Reliabilism. Nous 44 (4): 571–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin. 2001. Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1): 85–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Toward a Synthesis of Reliabilism and Evidentialism? Or: Evidentialism’s Troubles, Reliabilism’s Rescue Package. In Evidentialism and its Discontents, ed. Trent Dougherty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, John. 2000. Two Kinds of Intellectual Virtue. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 179–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Knowledge as Credit for True Belief. In Intellectual Virtue, ed. Michael DePaul and Linda Zagzebsky. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1967. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. In Hume’s Enquiries, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iqbal, Muhammad. 2012. The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Napier, Stephen. 2008. Virtue Epistemology: Motivation and Knowledge. Analysis Reviews 70 (3): 589–591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, Duncan. 2016. Seeing it for Oneself: Perceptual Knowledge, Understanding, and Intellectual Autonomy. Episteme 13 (1): 29–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, Fazlur. 2009. Major Themes of the Qur’an. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (originally published by Bibliotheca Islamica in 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Prophecy in Islam: Philosophy and Orthodoxy. revised ed. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, Wayne. 2007. Why Epistemologists Are so Down on their Luck. Synthese 158 (3): 336–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, Ernest. 1994. Virtue Perspectivism: A response to Foley and Fumerton. Philosophical Issues 5: 29–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Two False Dichotomies: Foundationalism/Coherentism and Internalism/Externalism. In Pyrrhonian Skepticism, ed. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, Richard. 2007. Revelation: From Metaphor to Analogy. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wahlberg, Mats. 2014. Revelation as Testimony: A Philosophical-Theological Study. Michigan/Cambridge: Eerdmans Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1995. Divine Discourse: Philosophical Reflections on the Claim that God Speaks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebsky, L. 1996. Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebsky, Linda. 2009. On Epistemology. Independence: Wadsworth, Cengage Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Trust. In Virtues and Their Vices, ed. Kevin Timpe and Craig A. Boyd, 270–283. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Adeel, M.A. (2019). The Qur’ānic Hints about Epistemic Responsibility: An Analysis of Etymological Variants of ‘i-l-m in the Text. In: Epistemology of the Quran. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 29. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-17558-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics