Skip to main content

Early and Late Vision: Their Processes and Epistemic Status

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Cognitive Penetrability and the Epistemic Role of Perception

Part of the book series: Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy ((PIIP))

Abstract

In this chapter, I elaborate my thesis that a stage of visual processing, namely, late vision, is Cognitively Penetrated (CP). The CP of late vision results in states with hybrid, that is visual/iconic and semantic/symbolic contents. The conceptual modulation of late vision notwithstanding, I argue that late vision is a perceptual stage rather than a stage of discursive thought. My main claim is that instead of discursive inferences, late vision involves pattern matching processes, and I discuss the perception of ambiguous figures to sybstantiate my claim. I also argue that early vision, too, does not involve discursive inferences and that both late and early vision involve some sort of abductive reasoning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Concepts are constant, context independent, and freely repeatable elements that figure constitutively in propositional contents; they correspond to lexical items.

  2. 2.

    The P3 waveform is elicited about 250–600 ms and is generated in many areas in the brain and is associated with cognitive processing and the subjects’ reports. P3 may signify the consolidation of the representation of the object(s) in working memory.

  3. 3.

    The view that the formation of the viewer independent representations of objects relies on object knowledge is common in theories of the formation of the 3D viewer independent representation. Biederman (1987) thinks that object recognition is based on part decomposition, the first stage in forming a structural description of an object. This decomposition cannot be determined by general principles reflecting the structure of the world alone, since the decomposition appears to depend upon knowledge of specific objects.

  4. 4.

    The phenomenal/non-phenomenal distinction is orthogonal to the discussion on mental imagery since mental imagery, exactly like perception, can either be accompanied by consciousness, or it can be implicit (as in implicit perception).

  5. 5.

    Gauker (2012, 45) reaches the same conclusion starting from a similar structural description of the perceptual system but without any mention of neural networks, although his construal of representations as marks and his discussion of perceptual similarity space in which these marks are located is close to the connectionist account I have sketched here.

  6. 6.

    For an elaborate treatment of proto-objects see Raftopoulos (2009).

  7. 7.

    In a de re belief, one retrieves information from the object itself and not through a description. In late vision where information in WM guides the formation of hypotheses about object identity, these hypotheses are based on descriptions in addition to visual information, since the knowledge stored in memory is a description of the object. Thus, the ensuing recognitional belief is based on a combination of information deriving from the object and from a description of it in memory. It is not a pure de re belief.

  8. 8.

    The view that the result of the conceptualization process occurring in perception can be described as a prima facie belief is explicitly endorsed by Gauker (2012, 45), and implicitly assumed by most among those who discus the epistemic role of perception in rationally supporting beliefs.

  9. 9.

    Nanay’s wording is very similar to Sellar’s (1977) explanation of the way the unseen parts of objects participate in the sense-image-model of the object that unifies contributions from the senses and the imagination. According to Sellars (1977)

    But while these features are not seen, they are not merely believed in. These features are present in the object of perception as actualities. They are present in virtue of being imagined.

    Sellars, unlike Nanay, however, thinks that the abovementioned remark applies to all cases of perception and not just to those in which imagination activates the visual cortex and gives rise to some sort of phenomenology, which is probably why Sellars says that these features are not seen. This immediately creates the problem (discussed by Coates 2007, 175–176) of how one should understand the claim that the unseen features of objects are present in the object of perception as actualities even in those cases in which imagination does not activate the visual cortex. When it does, there is a clear sense in which these properties are present in perception as actualities, as Nanay remarks, but when it does not, their presence as actualities needs explanation. Coates (2007, 177) proposes convincingly, that a way to understand Sellars is to think of the ‘presence as actuality of these features’ in terms of dispositional presence in the form of anticipations of the ways our phenomenal experience could be transformed should we, or the objects, move around and change the perspective from which the perceiver views the object. Such a change in perspective could render the hitherto unseen hidden parts of the object perceptible properties of the objects, which, thus, may be phenomenally experienced.

  10. 10.

    Note that Nanay (2010, 244) seems to talk about a perceptually driven amodal completion that is insensitive to other beliefs.

References

  • Andrews, T. J., Schluppeck, D., Homfray, D., Matthews, P., & Blakemore, C. (2002). Activity in the fusiform gyrus predicts conscious perception of Rubin’s vase-face illusion. Neuroimage, 17, 890–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barr, M. (2009). The proactive brain: Memory for predictions. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society London, B, Biological Sciences, 364, 1235–1243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2009). Perception and the reach of phenomenal content. Philosophical Quarterly, 39, 385–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, J. (2017). Marking the perception-cognition boundary: The criterion of stimulus-dependence. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2017.1329329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biederman, I. (1987). Recognition by components: A theory of human image understanding. Psychological Review, 94, 115–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2014). Seeing-as in the light of vision science. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(3), 560–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2014). What is inference? Philosophical Studies, 169(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borisyuk, R., Chik, D., & Kazanovich, Y. (2009). Visual perception of ambiguous figures: Synchronization based models. Biological Cybernetics, 100, 491–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. E. (2011). Mental imagery and the varieties of amodal perception. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 92, 153–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Britz, J., & Pitts, M. (2011). Perceptual reversals during binocular rivalry: ERP components and their concomitant source differences. Psychophysiology, 48, 1489–1498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2010). Strong representationalism and centered content. Philosophical Studies, 151, 373–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B., & Gatzia, D. (2017). Color and cognitive penetrability. Topics in Cognitive Science, 9(1), 193–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brossel. P. (2017). Rational relations between perception and belief: The case of color. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0359-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1977). Belief de re. Journal of Philosophy, 74, 338–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2003). Perceptual entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(3), 503–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2014). Reply to block: Adaptation and the upper border of perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(1), 573–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavanagh, P. (2011). Visual cognition. Vision Research, 51, 1538–1551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chelazzi, L., Miller, E., Duncan, J., & Desimone, R. (1993). A neural basis for visual search in inferior temporal cortex. Nature, 363, 345–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 181–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, P. (2007). The Metaphysics of Perception. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2008). Colour constancy as counterfactual. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 61–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corbetta, M., & Shulman, G. L. (2002). Control of goal-directed and stimulus-driven attention in the brain. National Review of Neuroscience, 3(3), 201–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delorme, A., Rousselet, G. A., Mace, M. J.-M., & Fabre-Thorpe, M. (2004). Interaction of top-down and bottom up processing in the fast visual analysis of natural scenes. Brain Research, 19, 103–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desimone, R., & Duncan, J. 1995. Neural mechanisms of selective visual attention. Annual Review of Neurosciences, 18, 193–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1993). Conscious experience. Mind, 102(406), 263–283. Reprinted in Noë and Thompson. (2002). Vision and Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996). Rethinking Innateness: A Connectionist Perspective on Development. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, W., & Broota, K. D. (1986). Automatic and attentional components in perception of size-at-a-distance. Perception Psychophysics, 40, 256–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabre-Thorpe, M., Delorme, A., Marlot, C., & Thorpe, S. (2001). A limit to the speed of processing in ultrarapid visual categorization of novel natural scenes. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 13, 171–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2007). The revenge of the given. In B. P. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Mind. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. (2012). Perception without propositions. Philosophical Perspectives, 26, Philosophy of Mind, 19–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzales-Cassilas, A., Parra, L., Avila-Contreras, C., Ramirez-Pedraza, R., Vargas, N., Luis del Valle-Padilla, J., & Ramos, F. (2018). Towards a model of visual recognition based on neuroscience. Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.bica.2018.07.018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granrud, C. E. (2004). Visual metacognition and the development of size constancy. In D. T. Levin (Ed.), Thinking and Seeing (pp. 75–95). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, G. (2002). Perception as unconscious inference. In D. Heyer & R. Mausfeld (Eds.), Perception and the Physical World: Psychological and Philosophical Issues in Perception. West Sussex: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, G. (2009). Perception and Cognition: Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. G., Jr. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the ‘space of reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109, 483–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. G., Jr. (2007). Are there different kinds of content? In J. Cohen & B. McLaughlin (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, von H. (1878[1925]). Treatise on Psychological Optics. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hochberg, J., & Peterson, M. A. (1987). Piecemeal organization and cognitive components in object perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 116, 370–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (1996). Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D (2003 [1739–1740]). A Treatise of Human Nature. Mineola, NY: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ito, J., Nikolaev, A. R., Luman, M., Aukes, M. F., Nakatani, C., & Van Leeuwen, C. (2003). Perceptual switching, eye movements, and the bus paradox. Perception, 32(6), 681–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1989). Consciousness and the Computational Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1977). Perception: A Representative Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, J. S., & Olshausen, B. A. (2005). The earliest EEG signatures of object recognition in a cued target task are postsensory. Journal of Vision, 5, 299–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2006). Better than mere knowledge: The function of sensory awareness. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual Experience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawabata, N. (1986). Attention and depth perception. Perception, 15, 563–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kihara, K., & Takeda, Y. (2010). Time course of the integration of spatial frequency-based information in natural scenes. Vision Research, 50, 2158–2162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornmeier, J., & Bach, M. (2009). Object perception: When our brain is impressed but we do not notice it. Journal of Vision, 9(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and Brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2007). Perceptual content is vertically articulate. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(4), 357–369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2015). Analog representation and the parts principle. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6, 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leopold, D. A., & Logothetis, N. K. (1999). Multistable phenomena: Changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Science, 3(7), 254–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ling, S., Liu, T., & Carrasco, M. (2009). How spatial and feature-based attention affect the gain and tuning of population responses. Vision Research, 49, 1194–1204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Long, G. M., & Toppino, C. T. (2004). Enduring interest in perceptual ambiguity: Alternating views of reversible figures. Psychological Bulletin, 130(5), 748–768.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. (1976). Problems from Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, B. (2018). Seemings as sui generis. Synthese, 195, 3079–3096.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2011). Reception as a Capacity for Knowledge. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2013a). Siegel and the impact for epistemological internalism. Philosophical Studies, 162(3), 723–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2013b). Phenomenal conservatism and cognitive penetration. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and Justification (pp. 225–247). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Meng, M., & Tong, F. (2004). Can attention selectively bias bistable perception? Journal of Vision, 4, 539–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millar, A. (2011). How visual perception yields reasons for belief. Philosophical Issues, 21, The Epistemology of Perception, 332–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, S. O. (2008). The effects of spatial attention in early human early visual cortex are stimulus independent. Journal of Vision, 8(10), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nakatani, H., & van Leeuwen, C. (2006). Transient synchrony of distant brain areas and perceptual switching in ambiguous figures. Biological Cybernetics, 94, 445–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). Perception and imagination: Amodal perception as mental imagery. Philosophical Studies, 150, 239–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2015). Perceptual content and the content of mental imagery. Philosophical Studies, 172, 1723–1736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noe, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, S. (1999). Vision Science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, M. A., & Gibson, B. S. (1991). Directing spatial attention within an object: Altering the functional equivalence of shape descriptions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 17, 170–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peyrin, C., Michel, C. M., Schwartz, S., Thut, G., Seghier, M., Landis, T., et al. (2010). The neural processes and timing of top-down processes during coarse-to-fine categorization of visual scenes: A combined fMRI and ERP study. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 22, 2678–2780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, B. (2017). The shifting border between perception and cognition. Nous, 1–31. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12218.

  • Pitts, M., Nerger, J., & Davis, T. J. R. (2007). Electrophysiological correlates of perceptual reversals for three different types of multistable images. Journal of Vision, 7(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, M. C., Wyble, B., Hagmann, C. E., & McCourt, E. S. (2014). Detecting meaning in RSVP at 13ms per picture. Attention, Perception, Psychophysics, 76, 270–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2002). Furnishing the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and Visualizing: It’s Not What You Think. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2009). Cognition and Perception: How Do Psychology and Neural Science Inform Philosophy? Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2010). Can nonconceptual content be stored in visual memory? Philosophical Psychology, 23(5), 639–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2014). The cognitive impenetrability of the content of early vision is a necessary and sufficient condition for purely nonconceptual content. Philosophical Psychology, 27(5), 601–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2015a). The cognitive impenetrability of perception and theory-ladenness. Journal of General Philosophy of Science, 46(1), 87–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2015b). Abductive inferences in late vision. In L. Magnani, W. Park, & Li Ping (Eds.), Philosophy and Cognitive Science II, Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics 20 (pp. 155–177). Basel, Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2017). Cognitive penetration lite and nonconceptual content. Erkenntnis, 82(5), 1097–1122. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9861-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A., & Muller, V. (2006). Nonconceptual demonstrative reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72(2), 251–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, M. (2009). Cognitive maps and the language of thought. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(2), 377–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, M. (2014). The causal relevance of content to computation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 173–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rock, I. (1983). The Logic of Perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roelfsema, P. R., Lamme, V. A. F., & Spekreijse, H. (1998). Object-based attention in the primary visual cortex of the macaque monkey. Nature, 395, 376–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2008). The situation dependency of perception. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 55–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1954). Physical realism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 15(1), 13–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Vol. I, pp. 253–329). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1977). Some reflections on perceptual consciousness. In R. Bruzina & B. Wilshire (Eds.), Selected Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy (pp. 169–185). The Hague: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1981). Foundations for the metaphysics of pure process (The Carus lectures). The Monist, 64, 3–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shams, L., & Beierholm, U. R. (2010). Causal inference in perception. Trends Cognitive Science (Regular Edition), 14, 425–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2006). On the way things appear. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual Experience (pp. 461–481). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual Experience (pp. 481–504). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2010). What Is Meaning? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S. (1988). Object perception. In A. I. Goldman (Ed.), Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science (pp. 447–461). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (2008). Our Knowledge of the Internal World. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1974). Imagination and perception. In P. Strawson (Ed.), Freedom and Resentment (pp. 45–65). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A Dynamic System Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toppino, T. (2003). Reversible-figure perception. Perception and Psychophysics, 65, 1285–1295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. (2006). How the deployment of attention determines what we see. Visual Cognition, 14, 411–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A., & Kanwisher, N. G. (1998). Perceiving visually presented objects: Recognition, awareness, and modularity. Current Opinions in Neurobiology, 8, 218–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, C. (2010). Why open-minded people should endorse dogmatism. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, Epistemology.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Kerkoerle, T., Self, M. W., Dagnino, B., Gariel-Mathis, M.-A., Poort, J., van der Togy, C., & Roelfsema, P. R. (2014). Alpha and gamma oscillations characterize feedback and feedforward processing in monkey visual cortex. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA (PNAS), 114(40), 14332–14341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Leeuwen, C., Steyvers, M., & Nooter, M. (1997). Stability and intermittency in large-scale coupled oscillator models for perceptual segmentation. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 41, 319–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamada, F. (1998). Frontal midline theta rhythm and eye linking activity during a VDT task and a video game. Ergonomics, 41, 678–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamagishi, N., Callan, D. E., Goda, N., Anderson, S. J., Yoshida, Y., & Kawato, M. (2003). Attentional modulation of oscillatory activity in human visual cortex. Neurotic Age, 20, 98–113.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Athanassios Raftopoulos .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Raftopoulos, A. (2019). Early and Late Vision: Their Processes and Epistemic Status. In: Cognitive Penetrability and the Epistemic Role of Perception. Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-10445-0_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics