Abstract
The standard Engineer-Lawyer problem (Kahneman & Tversky, 1973) points to the failure of reasoners to integrate mentioned base-rate information in arriving at likelihood estimates. Research in this area nevertheless has presupposed that participants respect complementarity (i.e., participants ensure that competing estimates add up to 100%). A survey of the literature leads us to doubt this presupposition. We propose that the participants’ non-normative performance on the standard Engineer- Lawyer problem reflects a reluctance to view the task probabilistically and that normative responses become more prominent as probabilistic aspects of the task do. In the present experiments, we manipulated two kinds of probabilistic cues and determined the extent to which (1) base rates were integrated and (2) the complementarity constraint was respected. In Experiment 1, six versions of an Engineer-Lawyer-type problem (that varied three levels of cue to complementarity and two base rates) were presented. The results showed that base-rate integration increased as cues to complementarity did. Experiment 2 confirmed that Gigerenzer, Hell, and Blank’s (1988) random-draw paradigm facilitates base-rate integration; a second measure revealed that it also prompts respect for complementarity. In Experiment 3, we replicated two of our main findings in one procedure while controlling for the potential influence of extraneous task features. We discuss approaches that describe how probabilistic cues might prompt normative responding.
Article PDF
References
Alberoni, F. (1962). Contribution to the study of subjective probability: Part I.Journal of General Psychology,66, 241–264.
Asare, S. K., &Wright, A. (1995). Normative and substantive exper tise in multiple hypotheses evaluation.Organizational Behavior & Human Decision Processes,3, 171–184.
Braine, M. D. S., Connell, J., Freitag, J., &O’Brien, D. P. (1990). Is the base rate fallacy an instance of asserting the consequent? In K. L. Gilhooly, M. T. G. Leane, R. H. Logie, & G. Erdos (Eds.),Lines of thinking: Reflections on the psychology of thought (Vol. 1, pp. 165–180). New York: Wiley.
Carroll, G. S., &Siegler, R. S. (1977). Strategies for the use of base rate information.Organizational Behavior & Human Performance,19, 392–402.
Cohen, J., Dearnaley, E. J., &Hansel, C. E. (1956). The addition of subjective probabilities.Acta Psychologica,12, 371–380.
Cosmides, L., &Tooby, J. (1996). Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions from the literature on judgement under uncertainty.Cognition,58, 1–73.
Davidson, D., &Hirtle, S. C. (1990). Effects of nondiscrepant and discrepant information on the use of base rates.American Journal of Psychology,103, 343–357.
Einhorn, H. J., &Hogarth, R. M. (1985). Ambiguity and uncertainty in probabilistic inference.Psychological Review,92, 433–461.
Fischhoff, B., &Bar-Hillel, M. (1984). Diagnosticity and the baserate effect.Memory & Cognition,12, 402–410.
Gigerenzer, G. (1991). How to make cognitive illusions disappear: Beyond “heuristics and biases.”European Review of Social Psychology,2, 83–115.
Gigerenzer, G. (1993). The bounded rationality of probabilistic mental models. In K. I. Manktelow & D. E. Over (Eds.),Rationality (pp. 284–313). London: Routledge.
Gigerenzer, G. (1994). Why the distinction between single-event probabilities and frequencies is important for psychology (and vice versa). In G. Wright & P. Ayton (Eds.),Subjective probability (pp. 129–162). New York: Wiley.
Gigerenzer, G. (1996). On narrow norm and vague heuristics: A reply to Kahneman and Tversky.Psychological Review,103, 592–596.
Gigerenzer, G., Hell, W., &Blank, H. (1988). Presentation and content: The use of base rates as a continuous variable.Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance,14, 513–525.
Gigerenzer, G., &Hoffrage, U. (1995). How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruction: Frequency formats.Psychological Review,102, 684–704.
Gigerenzer, G., Swijtink, Z., Porter, T., Daston, L., Beatty, J., &Kruger, L. (1989).The empire of chance: How probability changed science and everyday life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ginosar, Z., &Trope, Y. (1980). The effects of base rates and individuating information on judgments about another person.Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,16, 228–242.
Girotto, V. (1994).Il Ragiomento. Bologna: Il Mulino.
Griffin, D., & Dukeshire, S. (1992).On the use and neglect of base rates: A test of the visual random sampling hypothesis. Unpublished manuscript, University of Waterloo, Department of Psychology.
Hertwig, R., &Gigerenzer, G. (1999). The “conjunction fallacy” revisited: How intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors.Journal of Behavioral Decision Making,12, 275–305.
Hilton, D. (1995). The social context of reasoning: Conversational inference and rational judgment.Psychological Bulletin,118, 248–271.
Jones, S. K., Jones, K. T., &Frisch, D. (1995). Biases of probability assessment: A comparison of frequency and single case judgments.Organizational Behavior & Decision Processes,2, 109–122.
Kahneman, D., &Tversky, A. (1972). Subjective probability: A judgment of representativeness.Cognitive Psychology,3, 430–453.
Kahneman, D., &Tversky, A. (1973). On the psychology of prediction.Psychological Review,80, 237–251.
Koehler, J. J. (1996). The base rate fallacy reconsidered: Descriptive, normative and methodological challenges.Behavioral & Brain Sciences,19, 1–53.
Krosnick, J. A., Li, F., &Lehman, D. R. (1990). Conversational conventions, order of information acquisition, and the effect of base rates and individuating information on social judgments.Journal of Personality & Social Psychology,59, 1140–1152.
Macchi, L. (1994). On the communication and comprehension of probabilistic information.Psycoloquy [On-line serial],5(11), base-rate. 11.macchi.
Macchi, L. (1995). Pragmatic aspects of the base-rate fallacy.Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,48A, 188–207.
Marks, D. F., &Clarkson, J. K. (1972). An explanation of conservatism in the bookbag-and-pokerchips situations.Acta Psychologica,36, 145–160.
Noveck, I. A. (1997). Deductive competence need not be problematic: Some comments on Evan and Over’s proposal concerning human rationality.Current Psychology of Cognition,17, 162–172.
Piatelli-Palmarini, M. (1993).L’illusione di sapere. Milan: Arnoldo Mondadori.
Politzer, G., &Noveck, I. (1991). Are conjunction rule violations the result of conversational rule violations?Journal of Psycholinguistic Research,20, 83–103.
Schwarz, N., Strack, F., Hilton, D., &Naderer, G. (1991). Base rates, representativeness, and the logic of conversation: The contextual relevance of “irrelevant” information.Social Cognition,9, 67–83.
Slovic, P., Lichtenstein, S., &Fischhoff, B. (1988). Decision making. In R. Atkinson, R. J. Herrnstein, G. Lindzey, & R. D. Luce (Eds.),Stevens’s Handbook of experimental psychology, learning and cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 673–737). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sperber, D., Cara, F., &Girotto, V. (1995). Relevance theory explains the selection task.Cognition,57, 31–95.
Sperber, D., &Wilson, D. (1995).Relevance: Communication & cognition (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. (1st ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986)
Swieringa, R., Gibbins, M., Larsson, L., &Sweeney, J. L. (1976). Experiments in the heuristics of human information processing.Journal of Accounting Research,14 (Suppl.), 159–187.
Teigen, K. H. (1974). Overestimation of subjective probabilities.Scandinavian Journal of Psychology,15, 56–62.
Teigen, K. H. (1983). Studies in subjective probability III: The unimportance of alternatives.Scandinavian Journal of Psychology,24, 97–105.
Tversky, A., &Kahneman, D. (1982). Evidential impact of base rates. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.),Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases (pp. 153–160). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Van Wallendael, L. R., &Hastie, R. (1990). Tracing the footsteps of Sherlock Holmes: Cognitive representations of hypothesis testing.Memory & Cognition,18, 240–250.
Von Winterfeldt, D., &Edwards, W. (1986).Decision analysis and behavioral research. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wells, G. L., &Harvey, J. H. (1978). Naive attributors’ attributions and predictions: What is informative and when is an effect an effect?Journal of Personality & Social Psychology,36, 483–490.
Zukier, H., &Pepitone, A. (1984). Social roles and strategies in prediction: Some determinants of the use of base-rate information.Journal of Personality & Social Psychology,47, 349–360.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
This work was partially funded by a grant from DRET (La Direction de la Recherche et de la Technologie, 94/074) in France.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Baratgin, J., Noveck, I.A. Not only base rates are neglected in the Engineer-Lawyer problem: An investigation of reasoners’ underutilization of complementarity. Memory & Cognition 28, 79–91 (2000). https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03211578
Received:
Accepted:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03211578