Abstract
If entrepreneurship is amid jungle of theories and has many theorists, its social orientation or what is known as social entrepreneurship (SE) is amid arid land of theories and suffers under-theorizing which could be inherently stemmed from its diversely proposed definitions. To be situated in an embryonic pre-paradigmatic phase, getting to a more unanimous definition in this realm is the first step in laying a solid foundation for SE theorizing. As a pioneering study, the paper aims to investigate the epistemological foundations of SE definitions critically to propose a more convergent definition for SE. To fulfill this goal epistemological justifications for the definitional components of SE are presented. Therefore, it was necessary to rely on the relevant philosophical schools of thought in Epistemology (e.g. Empiricism, Internalism, Externalism, Verificationism and Falsificationism); first to discuss the controversies and oppositions to some components of the definitions for their exclusion and then to justify some other definitional components which are mostly accepted by the scholars for their inclusion in a final SE definition. Critical approach has helped us in specifying the maneuvering of thoughts in this field and determining the epistemological and definitional boundaries of SE. Finally, a more epistemologically-supported and justified definition was presented at the end of the paper. Moreover, one of the potential contributions of this paper could be its consensus-making impact among SE scholars in defining SE phenomenon, which could also pave the way for future theorizing in SE. The originality of the paper lies in the application of Internalism, Externalism, Verificationism and Falsificationism concepts to SE definitions.
“The most savage controversies are those about matters as to which there is no good evidence either way.” Bertrand Russell
Background
SE, which formed as a response to the state and market failures in tackling the social problems (Yujuico 2008; Nicholls 2006), needs careful philosophical scrutiny and thought to crystallize the conceptual boundaries and foundations of this phenomenon. According to Nicholls (2010), SE is “a field of action in a pre-paradigmatic state that currently lacks an established epistemology.” On the other hand, when we see divergent and heterogeneous definitions and research approaches by the scholars, the necessity and thirst for philosophical discussion of this entrepreneurial orientation emerges. Current loose definitions of SE have shaped a conundrum which is going to reveal itself not only in SE theorizing but also in SE practicing; especially in SE policy and decision making by either public or private, local or international organizations active in SE promotion. This condition is going to undermine any emerging SE academic legitimacy. A more recent example of controversy on the topic has arisen in the Asia Policy Dialogue (APD) held on Nov. 18, 2016 in Myanmar. The most controversial issue in APD, which absorbed much more attention, was how to define social enterprise and its related concepts, e.g. some of the participating investors and experts believed SE could be defined as a for-profit activity with “a revenue model” that “increases the abilities of the social enterprise to become a sustainable practice and create the incentives for founders as well as future investors.” However, the “proponents of limiting social entrepreneurs from reaping profits from their endeavors argued that the role of social enterprises is generating income for community not individuals and any profit made should be poured back into the enterprise itself” (Ahlden 2016). It reveals the SE definitional ambiguity had been contagious and has been spread to SE-related subjects on the operational levels such as social enterprise definition or social investment. Therefore, obscurity in defining SE has taken a root and it is going to show itself as a weed on the surface. Such congealed perplexity on the operational level could partially paralyze SE policy makers and planners and decrease their effectiveness. E.g. one of the universally known supporters for investment in SE was the Social Impact Investment Taskforce, which was announced on June 2013 at the G8 Social Impact Investment Forum. Currently the activities of the task force is transferred to and superseded by Global Social Impact Investment Steering Group (GSG).Footnote 1 The group consists of the EU plus 17 other countries. More recently in GSG Impact Summit 2017Footnote 2 the problem of social investment became controversial, e.g. there was a need to clarify by sharing “thoughts and ideas with practitioners (investees, aid agencies)” to help them “figure out what they want from investors.” Additionally, OECD countries are working on the true definition of Social Impact Investment (SII), as “the provision of finance to organizations addressing social needs with the explicit expectation of a measurable social, as well as financial, return” (OECD 2017).Footnote 3 Therefore, the recommendations provided by OECD reports on SII beside other necessities try to develop “a common agreement on definitions” as an orientation towards “furthering efforts on the measurement of social outcomes and evaluation of policy” (Ibid.). The variation in the definition of SE is also going to be used against SE legitimacy; especially in the media. For example, Shapiro (2013) in Forbes points out “the term social entrepreneurship has become somewhat of a catch-all phrase.” On the other hand, The Economist (2006) claims that “nobody is sure what exactly the term means”. Bornstein (2012) in The New York Times claims there is a new attention towards SE, but “with the new attention has come confusion about what social entrepreneurs do, however.” More harshly, Eppler (2012) believes SE “is the epitome of a buzzword; it is a term that means something slightly different to everyone and ultimately nothing to anyone, facilitating obfuscation and equivocation.” To be able to respond to such claims we believe a convergent definition of SE which has taken its constituting concepts from the current common ground among the SE scholars will neutralize future attribution of “obfuscation and equivocation” to the term SE. However, inability in reaching a common agreement on SE definition as a mother to all of the abovementioned issues would be making a structure on a shaky foundation. We do not expect a universally accepted definition of SE acts as a panacea but it could be the first step in overcoming the problem of ambivalent perceptions of SE. Epistemology as a philosophical concept to study the nature and essence of knowledge could be applied as a spur to encourage further discussions among the scholars on SE. Cukier et al. (2011) mention that Dees & Anderson (2006: 39) describe SE as an immature discipline and believe it “lacks the deep, rich, explanatory or prescriptive theories expected in a more mature academic field.” Organized knowledge is usually poured through theories, and those disciplines which are investigated more and scrutinized closely could have more sound and solid theories. SE suffers from lack of theorizing (Mair and Marti 2006; Dees and Anderson 2006; Nyssens 2006; Nicholls 2009) or as Dacin et al. (2010) puts, it is under-theorized. Pathologically, inability of SE in proposition of sound theories is an effect and symptom that demands careful probe for the diagnosis and determination of the cause(s). Deep down SE first needs to present a more consensus definition to be able to construct the wall of concepts and theories on a more sound foundation. We face numerous and in some cases contradictory definitions for this discipline. Lack of consensus on SE definitions originates from its blur boundary which consequently affects theorizing in its realm. Such discrepancy in definitions cannot lead to SE theory and originates Dees and Anderson’s (2006) attribution of “immaturity” to SE. Some blame the multiple domains such as for-profit, not-for profit and public sectors, used for the definition of the concept, for the nonexistence of a unifying definition (Weerawardena and Mort 2006; Christie and Honig 2006). Moreover, true endeavors in defining SE contribute greatly to the formation of an answer to how should we approach SE? (i.e. Is it a discipline which could define itself fully within its current boundaries? or is it an interdisciplinary realm with superseding boundaries?). In other words, should we define SE by and within entrepreneurship, sociology, management, economy and so forth? Such “lack of a common definition” also raised the question “which social or profit-making activities fall within the spectrum of social entrepreneurship” (Abu-Saifan 2012: 22) which intensifies the ambiguities in SE studies. Mainly, the scientific endeavor for SE definition has been necessarily but not sufficiently compensated by entrepreneurship scholars. However, SE fundamentally could benefit from two disciplines - a potential that is still intact: sociology to study its social aspects, and economics to study its entrepreneurial ones. SE as a discipline which tries to solve human being problems socially and entrepreneurially should assume human being first as a social being or homo sociologicusFootnote 4- but without that connotation of the word as “a simplified notion of the human individual in the foundations of sociological thinking, in which he/she is considered as unilaterally determined by social forces” (Subrt 2017: 242) and then as an economic being or homo economicus who is usually in economics literature seen as a “rational” being and makes his decisions based on “economic utility” (Frank 1987: 593). Nevertheless, human being is not always under “unilateral” social forces and as Frank (1987: 593) believed sometimes he violates rationality “without departing from utility-maximization” in his economic decision making; especially in case of entrepreneurship, and hence SE we see the phenomenon multilaterally within a wider scope of SE ecosystems. Unilateralism is doomed in social sciences’ epistemology and conceptualization, since there are numerous implicit and explicit forces in action to shape a social phenomenon. Entrepreneurship ecosystem “consists of a set of individual elements…that combine in complex ways” (Isenberg 2010: 3) or as defined by Stam and Spigel (2016: 1) “a set of interdependent actors and factors coordinated in such a way that they enable productive entrepreneurship within a particular territory,” evokes multilateral and systems thinking in any genuine endeavor for SE definition. Aristotle believed “man is a political animal” (Dixon and Wilson 2013: 1); in SE man should be seen simultaneously as a social and economic animal, i.e. a socio-economic one under the influence of socio-economic drives/forces. Therefore, sociology by studying SE in its social contexts and economics by giving careful consideration to social economics, social markets, and social innovation accompanied by knowledge of SE could help SE to reach a more scientific definition. Currently, SE is still “in the stage of conceptualization” (Sekliuckiene and Kisielius 2015: 1015) and true conceptualization starts from inclusive definition or redefinition of the phenomenon. Such a claim does not mean that there had not been any endeavor by the scholars for the definition, but it means the discrepancy of the definitions has led to a baffling degree that cannot help to an impartial student of SE to make the heads and tails of the phenomenon. First, the need for redefinition of SE should be found in the answer to the question: why SE has a large operational body (reflected by numerous national and international organizations which claim they are busy with SE activities such as Center for the Advancement of Social Entrepreneurship (CASE), Change.org, SEED Initiative, Ashoka.org, Skoll Foundation, Acumen, Echoing Green, Schwab Foundation for Social Entrepreneurship, some UN subsidiaries, etc.) and a fragile theoretical mind? The response is embedded in capitalist economy of the 1970’s, known in the USA as stagflationFootnote 5 with the worst situation of industrialist countries from the Great Depression (Frum 2000) which needed to wear a more humane disguise to be able to socially justify its existence against its approaching east-ward communist rival and fad.Footnote 6 Therefore, SE phrase was coined and raised in the U.S.Footnote 7 because there was a need for it. The emerging of the concept especially in the organizational context, started in the form of Corporate Social Responsibility (CSR) in large American companies to conciliate the social protests of their reluctance to environmental issues (Miller 2014) and the workers strikes (Tran 2015). Numerous papers have studied the similarities and differences of CSR and SE because of such affinities (e.g. Szegedi et al. 2016; Crisan and Borza 2012; Cornelius et al. 2008; Baron 2007). Therefore, the necessity for its existence induced its growth to be so speedy that did not let enough time for SE paradigm formation among the scholars which inherently affected its laggard in epistemological and hence definitional formations. The result was Nicholls’ (2010: 611) claim that SE is “in a pre-paradigmatic state that currently lacks an established epistemology” or Bacq and Janssen (2011) who describe SE with no “unifying paradigm.” Additionally, “its rapid growth” according to Newbert (2014: 239) “has resulted in a rather fragmented body of literature that lacks both a set of well-established theories and a robust, unified body of empirical research.” However, the early 80’s and 90’s connotative meaning of SE has started to be changed. Presently, social enterprise as one of the operational manifestation of SE, “has taken off as a new formula for success, combining capitalism with a do-gooder mentality” (Forbes 2016). The need for the redefinition of SE is more observable at the practical level rather than a theoretical one. Global and national policymakers need a more contingent and appropriate definition of SE to fit with the current world realities; i.e., “to tackle global issues such as alleviating hunger, improving education, and combating climate change” (Ibid.). Hence, primarily policymakers need to specify what the social role of entrepreneurship is. “Zahra and Wright (2016) argue that scholars need to re-examine and redefine the social role of entrepreneurship … They rely upon arguments from policymakers, world leaders and billionaire entrepreneurs, who advocate for a greater awareness of the potential downside to entrepreneurial activity. They surmise that scholars need to consider an entrepreneurial canvas focused on hybrid organizations pursuing the blended value that comes from corporate social responsibility and bottom-of-the-pyramid strategies” (Corbett 2016: 609). The re-modification of some traditional concepts of commercial entrepreneurship has already begun by SE. In 2012, the Credit Suisse Research Institute, in collaboration with the Schwab Foundation for Social Entrepreneurship at the World Economic Forum in Davos outlined the key features of their report entitled Investing for Impact: How social entrepreneurship is redefining the meaning of return. According to Rao (2012) “here, direct investments are made into social enterprises that provide scalable, self-sustaining solutions to address global problems. Examples include access to clean water, improved health care or the provision of clean energy. Such investments create a direct and measurable impact, as well as offer the potential for financial returns.” Such examples call for the adaptation of modern SE definition to be able to offer remedies to the emerging globalized challenges. On the other hand, SE itself is in a self-completing process by trial and errors. E.g. Michigan Corps, a non-profit launched in 2010, is going to give more prominence to the mission rather than the institution; therefore, “redefining social entrepreneurship, they announced their mission as purposely bringing local and global Michigander’s together to change their home state” (Tafel 2011). Anuja and Rishi Jaitly, the Michigan Corps’ founders believe, “we need to keep our eyes on the mission and off the perpetuation of one entity” (Ibid.). Furthermore, SE is going to be used as a role model for social practitioners to answer economic and social necessities synchronously. “Social workers today need to redefine their roles to include that of the social entrepreneurs;” because “the social worker’s response to the challenges of the new economic environment and globalization includes advocating for policies that promote social as well as economic development, social participation, and equality…The recognition for economics and social connectedness is vital” (Tan 2004: 87). Thus, SE should be refined, adapted and aligned as much as possible with global necessities by the scholars to be able to justify its role as a model for social value creating activities. In summary, redefinition of SE is inevitable based on the following discussed reasons:
-
(1)
Ameliorating and fixing Capitalism social reputation.
-
(2)
Fitting with the world realities for social policymaking.
-
(3)
Aligning with globalization and its social challenges.
-
(4)
Increasing its conduciveness as a role model for social remedy-finding endeavors.
On the other hand, Bacq and Janssen (2011) believe that there is a discrepancy in the perception of SE in Europe and America. Therefore, there is still an ongoing struggle for defining (Cukier et al. 2011) and making academic legitimacy for the phenomenon (Abu-Saifan 2012). Meanwhile, being poorly defined (Reis and Clohesy 2001; Weerawardena and Mort 2006; Zahra et al. 2009) and being deprived of a universally and academically accepted definition (Brooks 2009; Dacin et al. 2010; Short et al. 2009) justifies the necessity of the present paper. On the other hand, this jungle of definitions could be interpreted in two ways, either SE could not be a separate discipline from entrepreneurship or it embraces a very vast arena, which made the scholars to view it from different perspectives and provide such various definitions. It resembles the creature in the thirteenth century poem of the Persian philosopher and poet Rumi in The Masnavi, “The Blind Men and the Elephant”. Each blind man touches part of the creature and describes it as a tree, a trunk, a fan, a snake, etc. By analogy, “social entrepreneurship” phrase has taken numerous shades of meaning (Dees 1998b).This ambiguity in definitions and conceptual frameworks, pose the paper question:
What is a more epistemologically justified definition for SE?
Literature review
Epistemology is derived from two Greek words, episteme and logos, which means the knowledge of knowledge. Therefore it goes to the very foundation of how knowing is shaped; in other words, it deals with the pivotal foundation stone of our understanding. Human cognition process and what we call understanding and knowledge as its scientific fruit is basically a no man’s land. We have to base some a priori which itself needs to be explained. To what extent the presumed a priori is really relevant and scientific. What is our touchstone for their evaluation? Do we use knowledge to understand knowledge? What is the peg for the first knowledge (i.e. a priori) to hang our scientific discussions (i.e. posteriori) on? Hence, “the circularity of epistemology” is the response (Fig. 1). Johnson & Duberley (2000: 1) puts it as a paradoxical situation that epistemology cannot escape, “in that any theory of knowledge (i.e. any epistemology) presupposes knowledge of the conditions in which knowledge takes place.” In other words, it is entangled in a philosophical vicious circle. We have to take knowledge for the explanation and understanding of knowledge and that knowledge for another knowledge and so forth.Footnote 8
The circularity of epistemology. (Source: Johnson and Duberley 2000)
As Johnson and Duberley (2000) cited sea metaphor of Neurath (1944) in elaboration of the circularity of epistemology, “we are like sailors who on the open sea must reconstruct their ship but are never able to start afresh from the bottom.” According to Ashmore (1991: 787) it means, “the ship of knowledge must be repaired and even rebuilt on the open sea of social experience, there being no possibility of visiting any Archimedean dry dock.”
Circularity of entrepreneurship is the same as infinite images in two opposite mirrors (Fig. 2). Entrepreneurship always tries to know its orientations with the knowledge of entrepreneurship and could not exceed Schumpeterian-set foundations. Although it is a discipline which first originated out of economics, in its studies it is entangled in knowing itself by its own images and implicitly rejects any chances to step outside the circle to experience and benefit from other human knowledge.
To put the circularity of epistemology, as one of the main criticisms to epistemology itself, and circularity of entrepreneurship aside, epistemology could contribute us in our criticism on SE definitions. Additionally, to discuss the epistemological nature of SE definitions we face three concepts: Truth, Belief and Justification. Steup (2016) in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy explains these three concepts as, “False propositions cannot be known. Therefore, knowledge requires truth. A proposition S doesn’t even believe can’t be a proposition that S knows. Therefore, knowledge requires belief. Finally, S’s being correct in believing that p might merely be a matter of luck. Therefore, knowledge requires a third element, traditionally identified as justification;” then, he adds knowledge is “justified true belief: S knows that p if and only if p is true and S is justified in believing that p. According to this analysis, the three conditions - truth, belief, and justification - are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for knowledge.”Footnote 9 The concepts of truth and belief are extremely philosophical and somehow controversial issues in epistemology. The epistemologists usually go to the extremes to elaborate on these two requisites of knowledge which call for more sophisticated knowledge first in philosophy and then in epistemology. For example Audi (1988: 9) starts his discussions on the concept of belief by the nature of perception and mentions that some beliefs are propositional (their truth or falsity depends on the degree that our proposition about what we discuss is true or false). The other beliefs are objectual, “since it is a belief of an object.” Accordingly, we could have two types of perceptions: “propositional perception: perception that.” And “objectual perception: perception to be.” Such discussions could deviate us from the paper’s goal and because of their subtle and excessively abstract nature, entrap us in long and tedious elaborations. On the other hand, the general concept of justification for a non-philosophical reader is more tangible and easily comprehensible. Too much philosophizing on Truth and Belief as two presuppositions of knowledge which are inherently very abstract philosophical concepts left behind but the Justification concept because of its relevance to the concept of epistemological evidence is elaborated in respect to SE definitions. Therefore, for the elaboration of the epistemological criticism of the SE definitions we use the concept of “Justification” throughout the paper. We try to “justify” and support the relevant or reject the irrelevant SE components in the results and discussion section.
Frequently-referenced definitions of SE
Entrepreneurship itself is an “ill-defined and inherently complex” issue (Hoogendoorn 2011). Such dissensus of opinions in defining entrepreneurship (Lumpkin and Dess 1996; Van Praag 1999) is also conveyed to SE. Besides, SE is an “umbrella construct” which encompasses numerous phenomena (Hirsch and Levin 1999). These wide ranges of phenomena interfere in SE definition and accordingly beget diverse SE definitional components. Zeyen (2014) mentions 37 SE definitions counted by Dacin et al. (2010) and 20 definitions counted by Zahra et al. (2009). Table 1 has summarized some of the frequently-referenced definitions of SE. The relevancy and applicability of these SE definitional components are discussed at the results and discussion section of the article.
The frequently-mentioned characteristics of SE
The frequently-mentioned characteristics of SE as the end that SE is seeking are presented in Table 2.They reveal the justification for the existence of SE that should be reflected in its definitions.
Innovation and opportunity-seeking propensities are in common between commercial entrepreneurship and SE. What most of the researchers agree upon is the social intention of this orientation of entrepreneurship, which directs mind towards social context. Social knowledge like sociology and its relevant concepts such as sociometry,Footnote 10 socioeconomic and sociopolitical factors are necessary to understand the social contexts that SE is heavily dependent on; but in reality the great bulk of SE literature relies on entrepreneurship and management concepts. If SE intends to deal with the symptoms and their treatment (superstructure/effect) its current approach to social phenomena is satisfactory but if it intends to uproot and prevent social problems (substructure/cause)Footnote 11such as poverty, addiction, pollution, deforestation, war, etc. it is definitely on the wrong track. To address the root of the sociogenic problems, which SE is formed for their eradication or relief, it has to investigate them so much deep down. If commercial entrepreneurship is originated from economic thoughts, its social orientation is more akin to sociology, although it is neglected up to now, and maybe because of this negligence we do not have sound theories in and universal consensus on this realm. Therefore, the definitions of SE must have social orientation, since the ends that SE is seeking such as: making social change, social welfare, social value and social results are extremely socially-oriented topics. Accordingly the usage of “social concepts” in most of the definitions is justifiable.
Generalized SE definitional components
To apply each proposition (P1, P2, P3, P4) to all definitional components presented in Table 1 makes circumlocution and elongates the paper unnecessarily. Therefore, by considering the paper’s philosophy that is, “Determining the definitional components of SE phenomenon to be contributive in future theorizing of and consensus making in the discipline” and the paper’s goal which is “Presenting a final justified definition,” we have selected those components or definitional elements which have been common among the SE authors and prevailing in the SE literature for further discussions. To achieve this end the components are generalized into the following 6 items (Table 3). In other words, those components which have the same nature and meaning but uttered with different words are rounded off and poured within one phrase to be able to evade parallel discussions for similar components.
Methods
The philosophy of this paper is determining the definitional components of SE phenomenon to be contributive in future theorizing of the discipline. Therefore the aim of the research is the proposition of a more comprehensive and justified definition for SE that could potentially make a consensus among the SE scholars. To discuss the justifiability of different definitions, the paper has applied epistemological justification for SE definitional components. The rationale behind the selection of epistemology for SE definitions criticism is the application of this field of science for “justifiability” of human knowledge (Table 4). Thematic analysis as a qualitative method was initially used for deriving the “generalized definitional components” of SE out of the SE scholars’ proposed definitions for SE. The process of thematic analysis in this paper was done first inductively; i.e. through the results and discussion section “generalized definitional components,” which were extracted from (a) frequently-referenced SE definitions; and (b) frequently-mentioned characteristics of SE, were used to help the authors narrow down the realm of SE definitional phrases to be more concise and focused in their discussions on justification of the SE definitional components and second semantically, i.e. focused on the superficial, explicit meanings of the data and do not look beyond that or the connotative meanings (Boyatzis 1998).
On the next stage, for justifiable inclusion or exclusion of each “generalized definitional component” four epistemological propositions which are presented in Table 5 are put forward.
By applying the logic behind the abovementioned propositions (according to the presented flowchart in Fig. 3), logically consensus-making SE definitional components are determined to be used for a final epistemologically justifiable definition. Therefore the research question is:
SE definitional components’ distillation flowchart for inclusion or exclusion in a final epistemologically justified SE definition1. (Source: authors’ own work). 1“In a critical sense, Popper’s theory of demarcation is based upon his perception of the logical asymmetry which holds between verification and falsification: it is logically impossible to conclusively verify a universal proposition by reference to experience (as Hume saw clearly), but a single counter-instance conclusively falsifies the corresponding universal law. In a word, an exception, far from ‘proving’ a rule, conclusively refutes it.” (Thornton 2017)
What is a more epistemologically justified definition for SE?
Results and discussion
The definitional elements within SE definitions (Tables 1 and 2) could fall within one or some of the following epistemological schools of thought: Empiricism, Internalism, Externalism, Verificationism and Falsificationism. The rationale behind the choice of the abovementioned schools of thought in epistemology is the nature and type of the definitional components and attributed characteristics to SE by the scholars. In other words, the epistemological schools of thought are the touchstones for the justification of true and consensus-making components to be included in a final definition. Therefore, the intention behind these justifications is the final presentation of a more justified definition for SE. Global Entrepreneurship Monitor’s definition on SE, as a universally known organization in charge of entrepreneurship, is weighty and noticeable. GEM up to end of the year 2017, has released two reports on SE: one in 2009 and the other in 2016. In Global Entrepreneurship Monitor 2009: 8) “following the recommendation of several scholars (Short et al. 2009; Zahra et al., 2008),” the report offers a “broad definition that relates social entrepreneurship to individuals or organizations engaged in entrepreneurial activities with a social goal (Van de Ven, Sapienza and Villanueva, 2007).” Although “both the 2009 report and the current 2015 to 2016 report define social entrepreneurship quite broadly” (Global Entrepreneurship Monitor 2016: 9), Global Entrepreneurship Monitor 2009: 9) mentions three outstanding characteristics for social entrepreneurs which “distinguish social entrepreneurs from ‘regular’ entrepreneurs and/or traditional charities. In particular, three selection criteria seem to stand out in the extant literature: the predominance of a social mission, the importance of innovation and the role of earned income.” The subsequent Global Entrepreneurship Monitor 2016: 14-15) has identified seven characteristics as the main characteristics of SE: (1) “Social mission”; (2) “value creation”; (3) “value capture”; (4) “innovation”; (5) “reinvesting profit”; (6) “impact” and (7) “to be market-based”. Finally, Global Entrepreneurship Monitor 2016: 18) has evaded offering a comprehensive definition of SE and it was contended with following bipartite definition for SE: “(1) The organization is driven by (social) value creation, rather than value capture; and (2) The organization is market-based, rather than nonmarket-based.” However, it is the definition of social entrepreneurship organization (SEO) not SE. Concerning the definition, it is mentioned that “this narrow definition still allows for very different possible interpretations about what ‘social’ is and what ‘entrepreneurial’ means” (Global Entrepreneurship Monitor 2016: 18). Additionally, in the same GEM report on SE, “a social entrepreneur is defined as an individual who is starting or currently leading any kind of activity, organization or initiative that has a particularly social, environmental or community objective” (Global Entrepreneurship Monitor 2016: 9). According to Table 1 the most common concept among the SE definitions is the “social” attribution. Therefore SE has seen as “solutions to immediate social problems” (Alvord et al. 2004); “social value creating activity” (Austin et al. 2006; Peredo and McLean 2006);“[having]social missions” (Brouard et al. 2008; Lasprogata and Cotton 2003), “valued” (Dees 1998b) and “stimulating social change” (Mair and Marti 2006); “yield[ing] and sustain[ing] social benefits” (Fowler 2000), “[having] social objectives” Harding (2004),“us[ing] of entrepreneurial behavior for social ends” (Hibbert et al. 2005); “social wealth enhancement” (MacMilan, 2005); “developing a social value” (Martin and Osberg 2007); “recognis[ing] social value-creating opportunities”(Mort et al. 2002); “[leading to]transformative social change” (Roberts and Woods 2005); “working for social rather than only profit objectives” (Shaw 2004); “generat[ing] ‘entrepreneurial profit’ for a given social project” (Tracey and Jarvis 2007); “enhanc[ing] social wealth” (Zahra et al. 2009), etc. Accordingly, the concept of sociality should be seen as the first definitional component in the process of consensus-making, i.e. mostly the definitions are social in orientation. Metaphorically, as a snowball which roles down a hillside picks up more snow around the initial core, and hence momentum, the concept of sociality could be used as a core and gathers more thoughts around itself during the stages in the process of unanimity-making.Footnote 12 Organizing the SE definitional components around the concepts which are social can hasten the success in reaching a paradigm, and as the relevant concepts take form, it will take more velocity the same as the snowball that by getting bigger gets more acceleration. Therefore, every concept in SE could shape around “social” core and accordingly we will have social missions, social values, social changes, social results, social opportunities, social innovations and so forth (Fig. 4).
The snowball metaphor (Emerson & Twersky 1996). (Source: authors’ own work)
On the other hand the abundance of socially-oriented definitions among the proposed definitions for SE and the nature of SE as a social phenomenon, justifies the acceptance of sociology in SE studies and definitely pushes SE to be a more interdisciplinary discipline in respect to entrepreneurship.
SE concept is formed to be an effective response to the unsolved social problems (Yujuico 2008; Nicholls 2006; Alvord et al. 2004), therefore SE intention is pragmatic. Accordingly, in dealing with the type of justification suitable to SE, pragmatistFootnote 13 view is chosen by the paper’s authors. But before approaching the SE definitional components discussion we can have two propositions:
P 1 : Internal justification is suitable for the epistemological justification of SE definitional components.
P 2 : External justification is suitable for the epistemological justification of SE definitional components.
Epistemologists either take Internalism or Externalism for epistemic justification; accordingly the justification for SE definitional components could be dichotomous either internalist or externalist. These two propositions are “mutually exclusive”Footnote 14 so by scientifically defendable acceptance of one of them the other proposition / counterclaim will be excluded or rejected automatically. The juxtaposition of P1 and P2 is the starting point for the selection of suitable justification (internal or external) in our discussions.
Rejection of Internalist justification for SE definitional components
Internalist justifications cannot help the scholars in reaching a consensus in defining SE. Internalism claims that the justification of the belief is internal to the believer or subject. Goldman (1999) slashing criticism of Internalism in his paper Internalism Exposed rejects Internalism since it is “rife with problems”. One of the problems which could be also applied to SE definitions based on Goldman’s claim is the situation he arises. He believes, “two people in precisely the same evidential state (in terms of perceptual situation background beliefs and so on) might have different epistemic entitlements,” in other word they could have different justifications for the same body of evidence. Accordingly when SE scholars mention “social mission” (Mort et al. 2002; Lasprogata and Cotton 2003), “social transformation” (Alvord et al. 2004; Brouard et al. 2008), “social innovation” (Perrini and Vurro 2006), etc.; they pragmatically and internally try to justify the necessity of SE existence in their definitions based on its impact on society. Therefore, such examples call for reliance of SE definitions on scientifically collected data and evidence with requisite of external justifications; in other words the reasons of each diction (choice of words in definitions) should be outside the mental world of the definition proposer (by such an approach justifying SE definition will be as objective as possible). On the other hand, internalist approach to SE definition, creates different “epistemic values” which slacken the formation of a paradigm in SE. Different values magnify different definitional components which lead to perplexity and ambiguity. As Bonjour (2010) puts it, “on the externalist side, we have … the argument that internalism inevitably leads to skepticism.” Since Skepticism deals with doubts, on one hand it blocks the way to the formation of a consensus-making situation among SE scholars, and on the other hand lags the acquisition of unanimity in SE definition.
Mentalism
The type of Internalism which is unfortunately common among the scholars for the SE justification is Mentalism.
According to Conee & Feldman (2004: 55) mentalist justification deals with the entities “internal to the person’s mental life” and also with “occurrent and dispositional mental states, events, and conditions”. Usually, the SE scholars define SE differently and bold various keywords in this knowledge (Table 1). For example different scholars have seen a concept like “social change” as “social results” (Dees 1998a; Thake and Zadek 1997; Emerson & Twersky 1986), “social welfare” (Bugg-Levine et al. 2012; Scheuerle et al. 2013; Alvord et al. 2004; Battilana et al. 2012; Haigh and Hoffman 2012; Weisbrod 1977) or “social value” (Nicholls 2006; Dees 1998a; Gartener 1990; Hibbert et al. 2002; Austin et al. 2006; Boschee 1998; Alvord et al. 2004; Mort et al. 2002; Sarasvathy and Wicks 2003; Peredo and McLean 2006; Anderson and Dees 2002; Townsend and Hart 2008; Matin 2004). Therefore, their justifications for the inclusion of definitional components mostly originate from internal and subjective grasp of the phenomenon. Such discrepancy could be stemmed from different “mental state[s] of the epistemic agent[s]” (Pappas 2014). How could SE scholars define the same thing but have different mental states towards it? It could be answered if we consider their justification of SE belief first internal and then mental, in other words different states of mind led to different definitions which show different justifications for the belief in knowing the entity that they define, hence SE. Therefore, they usually define their mental grasps of SE not the external social realities. That is the main reason for inability of the SE discipline in reaching a paradigm. On the other hand, in defining SE we have got to deal with “what is, not for what”Footnote 15 we think should be; therefore reliance on Mentalism (because of the changing propensity of the ideas by age, experience, scientific background, and the potential “implicit bias”Footnote 16) sets SE definitions on a flaky and simultaneously shaky foundation. In contrary, we should establish the definitional structure on a solid foundation which does not change from person to person. Such a foundation ought to be chosen from the concrete reality in the real world, not the idealistic mind of the proposer, a reality which has one or most of the features such as tangibility, sensibility, observability and scalablility. Internalist justification, hence because of its reliance on mere cognitive and mental perception of the scholar potentially results in more dissonance in the definition of SE.A good example for such Mentalism is seen in the sectors that SE could happen. According to Austin et al. (2006) “SE is an innovative, social value creating activity that can occur within or across the nonprofit, business, or government sectors;” or Yunus (2008), in defining SE believes, “The initiative may be economic or non-economic, for-profit or not-for-profit”; while Lasprogata and Cotton (2003), define SE as “nonprofit organizations” and reject the other possible sectors and organizational forms. In real world, we can see obviously that SE could happen in any sectors; therefore exclusion of some sectors and accentuation of only one sector is an idealistic Mentalism. It is the same as the well-known Francis Bacon’s anecdote dealing with the discussion among some philosophers on the number of horse’s teeth. Each one of them based on deduction tried to say a number. After some days of quarrel among them which was originated from reluctance to count the teeth of a real horse somebody suggested to open the mouth of a horse and count his teeth. In reality, SE could take place in any sector, but idealistically its realm is not-for-profit.
Another reason to the vast arena of mental states in defining SE among the SE scholars could be Contextualism. Based on different local, economic and social “contexts” scholars have had various attribution of definitional components to SE, which is stemmed from numerous cognitive perceptions of “knowings” in respect to SE. In Contextualism, “the truth conditions for sentences containing the word “knows” vary from one context to another” (Feldman 2010). The result of such a situation had been the production of a spectrum of shades of meaning for SE. Therefore, an SE scholar in Iran with different socio-economic and cultural context potentially defines SE different from the definition of his colleague for instance in Canada. So, when we say we “know” what SE is, the word “know” cognates with economic, social, and cultural contexts which begets the type of the SE that the subject “knows”. Accordingly, SE in the American context is different from the SE in the European one (Nyssens 2006; Kerlin 2006). Each context bolds certain characteristics of SE, for example in the American context SE takes place in social enterprises that emphasizes revenue generating exercises (Kerlin 2006) and it is extremely market-oriented (Nyssens 2006). On the other hand, in the European context SE mostly defines in and deals with the third sector and acts within social economy (Hoogendoorn et al. 2010) and the social enterprises which are implementing SE are active in not-for-profit sector (Nyssens 2006). Some authors such as Urban (2008) substituted the word “environment” for context. He believes SE, “can be viewed as a process that serves as catalyst for social change, and varies according to socio-economic and cultural environments” (Urban 2008); or for example Weerawardena and Mort (2006) believe that SE concept must be understood within “competitive environment”. Dealing with SE contextually results in disparity in definitions. Metaphorically, SE changes into a chameleon which takes different colors by standing on different contexts (environments). It could be seen as one of the principal barriers to the formation of a universal or semi-universal definition for SE and on the way to SE paradigm formation as well.
SE is defined in different sectors which based on the defining context and ground has taken the necessary attributes to be able to be defined in that context. Therefore SE in not-for-profit sector could be potentially different to the SE in for-profit sector or in public sector. Hence, SE reveals itself as, “a multi-interpretable concept” (Hoogendoorn et al. 2010). Some authors (Fowler 2000; Boschee & McClurg, 2003; Reis and Clohesy 2001) define SE in not-for profit sector and some others define it in for-profit sector but with social intentions (Johnson 2000; Leimsider 2014; Lapowsky 2011) or believe they are “starting for-profit” regardless of their present sector (Dees 1998b)(Fig. 5). Contextualist spectrum of shades of meaning for SE takes the most extensive form in Nicholls (2006) definition of the phenomenon as, “an umbrella term for a considerable range of innovative and dynamic international praxis and discourse in the social and environmental sector.”
A contextualist spectrum of shades of meaning for sector-related SE as an example of Mentalism. (Source: authors’ own work). 1Dees did not limit SE to any specific sectors. He believed,“ In addition to innovative not-for-profit ventures, social entrepreneurship can include social purpose business ventures, such as for-profit community development banks, and hybrid organizations mixing not-for-profit and for-profit elements, such as homeless shelters that start businesses to train and employ their residents ” (Dees 1998b)
“Soft knows” consist of a range of “knows” in defining SE. Such a situation is common in pre-paradigmatic fields of knowledge, since each scholar “knows” and accordingly defines the phenomenon differently. As the “soft knows” narrow down to a fewer scientifically supported and more consensus “hard knows” it takes a more paradigmatically defined form. Such a situation in the future as any field of knowledge will potentially occur to SE too. At the base of the pyramid we face numerous and sometimes contradictory definitions for SE (Fig. 6). In respect to SE definition, the current situation is at the base of the pyramid, and thus the SE definitions are bearing a pre-paradigmatic sense. We can attribute to the peak and the base of the pyramid according to Feldman’s (2010) discussion “strong sense” and “weak sense” of “knows” respectively. He believes, “in its strong sense knows” requires something like absolute certainty … “in its weak sense, it requires strong reasons of the sort we often do have.” Because of this necessity to provision of “reasons” for the “weak sense” of “knows” in SE definitional components that verification and falsification as two reasoning tools are used in this paper.
Mostly the SE authors have defined their own subjectively mental visions instead of the objective reality of SE. Such a situation recalls the Platonic example of the cave and the shadows.Footnote 17SE authors have usually dealt with the effect not the cause. They had been busy with the cast of the shadows on the wall of the cave and they did not try to come out of the cave to face the true existence of SE. Dees (1998b) after presenting its pentagonal definitionFootnote 18 of social entrepreneurs believed, “This is clearly an ‘idealized’ definition. Social sector leaders will exemplify these characteristics in different ways and to different degrees.” Another idealism which has seen in SE literature is a tendency to show social entrepreneurs as heroes (Dacin et al. 2011) and SE as an act of heroism and accordingly they claim that such world-saving and world-changing attributions which sometimes attributed to social entrepreneurs is an, “idealistic assumption” about them which, “is misleading because it confounds issues of ability with issues of motivation and interest.” On the other hand, one of the reasons that makes SE definition hard is the fact that, “there is no proven method, code of practice or core business model to follow” in SE (Roberts and Woods 2005) which inherently originates from lack of paradigm.
Supporting externalist justification for SE definitional components
To justify the applicability of the definitional component to SE we have to take externalist justification. According to externalists there is no need for cognitive grasp or internal access to reasons or facts to make what somebody believes justified (Bonjour 2008). In other words, the justification of belief, in Externalism, begets from the facts and reasons, which are completely external to “the agent’s subjective awareness” (Sosa et al. 2008). Externally justified definitions of SE should deal with non-mental entities, the factual and scientific entities in the real world. Such definitions of SE should have “an externalist view” which according to Bonjour (2010), “allows some element that is essential to the cogency of a justificatory reason to be outside of, external to, the person’s cognitive perspective.”
Providing some successful SE examples like Aravind Eye ClinicFootnote 19 in India, MahakFootnote 20 charity for children who are diagnosed with cancer in Iran, Grameen BankFootnote 21 in Bangladesh, AshokaFootnote 22 and so many other examples in the world out there, is helping us to take externalist justification. Such examples provide sufficient facts to justify the existence of an orientation of entrepreneurship with socially practical outcomes. To specify and narrow down the type of Externalism which is discussed in the above lines we should claim that Aravind Eye Clinic, Mahak, Grameen Bank and Ashoka are some of the successful evidences and examples that SE seeks for as “social changes”. These examples are social changes which supports EvidentialistFootnote 23 Externalism for justification of SE definitional components. It is evidentialist since it is based on tangible life-like examples and it is externalist because it does not pursue mental concepts for the justification of SE but on the contrary the observable axiomatic instances of SE.
Reliabilism
Reliabilism is an externalist justification approach. In Reliabilism a belief considers to be justified if it is based on a reliable cognitive process. This reliability deals with and contributes to the formation of what Goldman’s (2010) key phrase calls “truth-conduciveness of a person’s reasons”. Reliabilist definition of SE has a key condition. Initially the input or data gathering and observations must be based on scientific methodologies and approaches. Otherwise even if SE scholar has the sharpest and brilliant mind the result will be garbage in, garbage out and hence unjustified definition or a far-fetched definition of SE (Fig. 7).
Externalist justification helps SE scholars to be “objective” in their choice of true SE definitional components. According to Audi (2010: 558) “the subjective-objective contrast arises above all for the concept of justification”. He believes that, “externalism, particularly reliabilism, construes justification objectivistically, since for reliabilism truth-conduciveness (non-subjectivity conceived) is central for justified belief.”
Moreover, “concrete definitions” will contribute to “overcome the vagueness of the concept of social entrepreneurship” (Certo and Miller 2008: 267). Concrete definition calls for concrete, externalistically justified and empirically verified definitional components. We cannot present a hard and fast definition of SE unless we achieve the true and tangible constituents of the SE.
Therefore, we reject:
P 1 : Internal justification is suitable for the epistemological justification of SE definitional components.
And based on “mutual exclusivity” logic and the aforementioned discussions, we accept:
P 2 : External justification is suitable for the epistemological justification of SE definitional components.
Furthermore, by accepting P2, we could be more focused in our discussion, and then we should accept the epistemological schools of thought which emphasize externally tangible and sensory reasons for the justification of SE definitional components. Hence, Empiricism because of its emphasis on experience and experiment is one of the possible acceptable schools of thought for external justification.
Empirical definition of SE
Empiricism is a school of thought which claims that knowledge merely originates and comes from sensory experience (Psillos and Curd 2010), that is, “empiricists draw the moral that the social sciences can and should cease to use mental concepts in explanation, replacing them by genuinely scientific explanations” (Lessnoff 1974). Basically empirical researches in SE are meager. According to Short et al.’s (2009: 161) study “conceptual articles outnumber empirical studies, and empirical efforts often lack formal hypotheses and rigorous methods. These findings suggest that social entrepreneurship research remains in an embryonic state.” Granados et al. (2011) and Sassmannshausen and Volkmann (2013) also demonstrated that mostly SE papers with high citations did not have empirical sections and had usually used qualitative approaches. On the other hand, in the realm of SE conceptual papers had been dominant (Hoogendoorn et al. 2010). Additionally, “its rapid growth” according to Newbert (2014: 239) has resulted in lacking of “a robust, unified body of empirical research.” Therefore, it will be hard to specify to what extent has the application and theorization of the concept of social entrepreneurship led to different empirical outcomes.
Empirically, we can put forward two supplementary propositions: P3 for verification and P4 for falsification of SE definitional components. The propositions are explained under the following subheadings:
Verification of SE definitional components
P 3 : If a definitional component of SE could be proved to be either true (verifiable) or false (falsifiable) then it should be studied; otherwise it is cognitively meaningless.
Sensory experience has seen as the source of knowledge. Through Logical Empiricism (Logical Positivism) the emphasis on sensory experience took a vigorous form. The outcome was Verificationism, a view which asserts only the statements that are empirically verifiable are cognitively meaningful; in other words, statements or philosophical propositions must be either true (verifiable) or false (falsifiable); otherwise they are meaningless and nonscientific.
In a scientific point of view, SE is not a moralist’s or utopian socialist’s entity, but it seeks social impact and if it has such an intention, it should be empirically and socially tangible and observable, that is, each SE component and claim must be verifiable; otherwise it is cognitively meaningless. Application of verification to SE definitional components does not mean to fall into Mathematicism or Physicism to verify SE suitable components for its definition but it accentuates that in defining SE we must be logically “scientific”, in a sense that SE definitional components being supported by cogent scientific logic (e.g. facts, data and appropriate methodologies).
I. Verification of “social mission”
Dees (1998b) in his influential paper The Meaning of Social Entrepreneurship truly believed, “any definition of social entrepreneurship should reflect the need for a substitute for the market discipline that works for business entrepreneurs.” He believes although social entrepreneurs are active in a market; the concept of the market is different from the conventional type of entrepreneurship. The markets for social entrepreneurs are mission-oriented, not financially-oriented and seek “mission-related impact” in the community and also the estimation of how much social value is made in SE by the application of market resources is a challenging issue. Such a view gives prominence to the role of social mission in determination of who and how should be served. Therefore, he prioritizes, “Adopting a mission to create and sustain social value (not just private value)” as the first of the five items that he presumes for a social entrepreneur as a “change agent”.Footnote 24 The importance of SE definitions which are mission-oriented is also reflected in the summary of Dacin et al.’s (2011) paper. They believed, “a mission-focused definition of social entrepreneurship provides the field with the potential to offer something unique to organization science.”
“Social mission” could be verified if it is reflected in the mission statement of the SEO; otherwise it could not be applied in the strategic planning of the organization.Footnote 25 Each organization’s strategic planning determines the policies and accordingly the operational plans to implement the formulated strategies. Therefore, a socially entrepreneurial organization or agency must have a social mission statement. In the absence of such a social mission statement, sometimes the organization acts a socially entrepreneurial one and in many other cases there would not be any guaranties to behave as an SEO. Having social mission to be included in SE definitions is cognitively meaningful. Therefore, we can assert the justification as:
Since all SEOs have “social mission statement” (SMT) and all non-SEOs feel no necessity to have a persistent social mission that was translated and uttered in their mission statements, Footnote 26 social mission(SM) is the drive which pushes the organizations and agencies towards social commitment to the society or community and it is a definitional component of SE. Footnote 27
II. Verification of “social innovation”
Since SE is a form of entrepreneurship, it must deal with a form of “innovation”. The presence of innovation to SE is so pivotal and vital that it could not be defined without it. Innovation is the most fundamental concept for any form of entrepreneurship and accordingly for SE too (Schumpeter 1951; Drucker 1985; Herbert and Link 1989; Nijkamp 2000; Galindo and Mendez 2008; Covin and Slevin 1991; Lumpkin and Dess 1996; Morris and Kuratko 2002; Kuratko et al., 2005; Zakić et al. 2008; Miller and Friesen 1982; Covin and Miles 1999; Burgelman 1984; Kanter 1985; Alterowitz 1988; Naman and Slevin 1993; Zahra and Covin 1995; Rwigema and Venter 2004; Slater and Narver 2000; Smart and Conant 1994; Lumpkin and Dess 1996; Ussahawanitchakit 2007; Mohd Osman et al. 2011; Salarzehi and Forouharfar 2011). The type of innovation that SE should seek is an external type of innovation. It means there should be tangible and sensible innovation which could be seen or felt easily in society. It is a must to feel and see the innovation easily otherwise it is a theoretical creativity, an idea that demands a social entrepreneur to translate it into practical innovation. Moreover, the relevance of innovations to “society”, justifies the application of “social” for the innovations. The innovations in SE are social innovations (Sheldon and Daniele 2017; Perrini and Vurro 2006), i.e. the innovations which are practical and have been implemented in society. Therefore, we can assert the justification logic as:
Since SE is an orientation of entrepreneurship (E) and “innovation” (I) is an inseparable and irrefragable component of entrepreneurship, then the social orientation of entrepreneurship (SE) should also have innovation in its nature and because it is active in the social realm, the kind of innovation that SE deals with must be “social innovation” (SI).
III. Verification of “transformative social change”
“Social change”(Nicholls and Cho 2006; Skoll Foundation 2008; Prabhu 1999; Hoffman et al. 2010; Choi and Gray 2008; Cohen and Winn 2007; Waddock and Post 1991; Stryjan 2006; Picot 2012) is a definitional component of SE. Social change is inherently against the status quo. When the status quo stays for a long time its deficit functions in the social arena make some deprivations for some individuals or a group of people or result in some catastrophic environmental, economic, political or social effects. SE is naturally a reaction to the embedded social malfunction and tries to transform it to a better and socially, environmentally, politically, or economically beneficial status. Therefore, we can assert the justification logic as:
Change is the result of any entrepreneurship. Footnote 28 The change that entrepreneurship seeks is unbalancing the current equilibrium (disequilibrium, D). SE also tries to make a new and fair equilibrium by destroying and toppling the current unjustified order (social disequilibrium, SD) which is envisaged in social segregations, deprivations, injustice, etc. Then it is a change which is social(SC) and since it is unbalancing the status quo (equilibrium) it is transformative(T), in other words, it is transformative social change (TSC).
IV. Verification of “recognition of social value-creating opportunities”
Social value assessment is an abstract issue which is very hard to be measured or to be determined. Emerson (2003) believes, “most elements of social value stand beyond measurement and quantification”. Dees (1998b) has mentioned the hard task of determining economic utilityFootnote 29 of social value creation by SE since social entrepreneurs’ markets are different from the commercial ones:
“With business entrepreneurs, wealth creation is a way of measuring value creation… Markets are not perfect, but over the long haul, they work reasonably well as a test of private value creation, specifically the creation of value for customers who are willing and able to pay… Markets do not work as well for social entrepreneurs. In particular, markets do not do a good job of valuing social improvements, public goods and harms, and benefits for people who cannot afford to pay. These elements are often essential to social entrepreneurship. That is what makes it social entrepreneurship. As a result, it is much harder to determine whether a social entrepreneur is creating sufficient social value to justify the resources used in creating that value.”
Additionally, sometimes economic utility is in contrast to social utility, as Christlieb (2012) mentions, “Santos 2012 points to the example of the Mexican bank Compartamos and argues that an enterprise needs to decide whether the focus is on the creation of social or economic value.”
Hlady-Rispal and Servantie (2016), in the paper Deconstructing the way in which value is created in the context of social entrepreneurship asserted that: “within empirical or conceptual studies, almost all authors use the term ‘value’, but seemingly assume the dimensions of value rather than define or analyze its connotations and components.” Such multi-dimensional connotative “values” in SE has taken mentalist interpretations.Footnote 30 Their belief of, “all authors use the term ‘value’, but seemingly assume the dimensions” is a hint for our attribution of Mentalism to “value” in SE literature (e.g. Certo and Miller (2008) define social value as, “the fulfillment of basic and long-standing needs”, and in Thake and Zadek (1997) as reduction of inequalities or resolving social problems by Drayton (2002)).These connotations reveal the ambiguity of the concept. Measurability of value-creation for a social opportunity is tougher. It is very hard to assess how much value-creation is potentially in a social opportunity.
Finally, it is very hard to empirically verify “social value creation” by SE opportunities since it is a mentalist assertion. Based on the rejection of proposition 1 (P1) (internalist Mentalism is rejectable) and the acceptance of proposition 2 (P2), (the acceptance of externalist justification) we should claim that because of immeasurability and indescribability of social value it is not possible to be justified externally, and it needs to be justified by mental states of the authors and on such a ground it is an internal justification and so rejectable. In other words:
“Social value creation” (SVC) for social opportunities could have logically empirical acceptance if and only if it applies externalist justification (EJ) and since it cannot be justified by the externalist justification but its needs its contrary (internalist justification, IJ) then it is rejectable as a paradigm-making and tangible SE component and it is going to be eliminated in our final SE definition.
One of the attributed characteristics to any entrepreneurship (E) is opportunity-seeking (OS). SE is an entrepreneurship with social objectives which is active in the social realm, therefore the nature of the opportunities that SE seeks must be social (social opportunity seeking, SOS) since it finds its opportunities in the society and applies those opportunities for social benefits.
V. Verification of “not to be sector-bound”
According to Table 1 and summation of different authors’ observations of SE in different sectors (Not-for-profit; e.g. Fowler 2000; Dees 1998b; Boschee & McClurg, 2003; Reis and Clohesy 2001; Hybrid; e.g. Dees 1998b; Blanding 2013; Battilana et al. 2012 and For-profit; e.g. Dees 1998b, Johnson 2000; Leimsider 2014), it could be claimed that:
SE could be seen in public (PUB.S), private (PRI.S), for-profit (FP.S), and not-for-profit (NFP.S) sectors, therefore, it is not bound to the sector (S).
VI. Verification of “to be creative”
Change is the result of any entrepreneurship or according to Schumpeter, entrepreneurship (E) has “creative destruction”(CD), since on one hand SE is entrepreneurship, and on the other hand, innovation(I) is one of the fundamental traits to any entrepreneurship and any innovation needs creativity (C) then SE needs creativity too.
Finally, the following SE definitional components are logically verifiable:
-
1.
“social mission”
-
2.
“social innovation”
-
3.
“transformative social change”
-
4.
“recognition of social opportunities”
-
5.
“not to be sector-bound”
-
6.
“to be creative”
And, as it was elaborated under its relevant heading, “Value-Creation” which was attributed to “social opportunities” is not verifiable on the ground that it requires internal justification which leads to Mentalism.
The abovementioned components are discussed in the next section for falsifiability.
Falsification of SE definitional components
P 4 : If a definitional component of SE could be proved not to be false then it is true.
Karl Popper’s Falsificationism as a distinguishing factor between scientific and unscientific claims is a touchstone for us to distinguish true SE definitional components from the false ones. According to Popper; we should search for falsifiable issues. We should try to falsify them by “counter-evidence” and “those which survive testing should then be tentatively accepted and regarded as corroborated or closer to the truth than the ones which have been falsified” (O’Hear 2010). By providing “counter-evidence” cases for each SE definitional component, we can test their falsifiability and avoidance of pseudo-components. In other words, falsification could be used here as a reasoning tool for the acceptance or rejection of SE definitional components.
If an asserted SE component in the definitions deals with what “should be” or falls into “moral biases”, because of being heavily subjective or mentalist interpretation of the SE phenomenon, it will be rejected before any discussion for falsifiability.
I. Falsification of “social mission”
Non-socially entrepreneurial organizations have not a “social mission statement”, so all SE which takes place by organizations, if is conditioned to be persistent, need to have “social mission statement”.
All non-SEOs (NSEO) do not have a social mission statement (SMT) and accordingly do not act socially entrepreneurial (SE). Therefore; in contrast SEOs have a “social mission statement” and accordingly define their strategic views based on “social missions”.
II. Falsification of “social innovation”
ᅟ
All SE begets social innovations.
SE → SI
Concerning the contextual SE presented in Fig. 6 (dealing with “hard knows” and “soft knows” as two contextual understanding of the concepts soft “social” and hard “social”) we can have two different types of innovations in SE which are discussed in the following:
Soft knows
Although SE in many cases brings social innovation to society, as it was asserted briefly, there are some other possible cases too; for example, ecological or environmental innovations which are not “social”; in a sense that, they are not directly related to human society or human social life (e.g. treating sick animals in an organization such as World Organization for Animal HealthFootnote 31 or trying to help endangered animals and prevent their extinctions in World Wildlife FundFootnote 32 or preserving jungles in an organization such as Rainforest Foundation USFootnote 33 or UN EnvironmentFootnote 34 and natural, cultural or historical preservatory activities such as in UNESCO’s World Heritage FundFootnote 35 all could be stereotype examples of the realms that we could find SE). “Soft knows” extend the meaning of the term “social” in SE. Therefore the claim that, “All SE begets social innovations (SE→SI)” is falsifiable or refutable on the ground that there is SE in the real world which makes environmental, ecological, preservative, and some other animate being-oriented innovations. Therefore, it is better to modify that claim as:
All SE begets innovations benefiting live beings for a better existence (in other words, innovation for better existence, IFBE).
Such a claim can broaden and extend the hug of SE to really embrace what it really does, it means SE is not only active in the social realm and human being lives but also in all other fields which contribute to the existence and rehabilitation or conservation of other animate beings.
Hard knows
If we limit the realm of SE only to the social realm and define other entrepreneurship such as Ecopreneurship,Footnote 36 Green Entrepreneurship, and Sustainopreneurship for the aforementioned cases; then the first claim could not be falsified, therefore we accept the following logic conditionallyFootnote 37:
All SE begets social innovations.
SE → SI
In other words, lack of social innovation (SI) leads to lack of SE.
¬SI → ¬SE
According to Fig. 6 dealing with “hard knows” and “soft knows” as two contextual understanding of the concepts in SE we can look at the word “social” in the phrase “social entrepreneurship” as hard (limited and specific) or soft (extended meaning which embraces environmental, ecological and other animate beings) (Fig. 8) and accordingly by narrowing down the concept of “social” and ascending the triangle (limiting and specifying our cognition) we could have a hard and fast knowledge of the word “social” and based on it define “social” only in the realm of society and thus the innovation which takes place in SE merely as “society-oriented innovation” and innovation must be defined as “social innovation” (SI). On the other hand as we descend the triangle, the soft concept of “social” is intensified and could include the other animate beings such as animals and plants or entities which contribute to the ecologies such as earth and its preservation; therefore any movement towards the facilitation and improvement of these entities could also count as “social” concept in its extended meaning. The hard concept of “social” in SE as it was shown is verifiable and not falsifiable, but the soft concept of “social” in the phrase SE is refutable to be used as a definitional component except we define the type of innovation that it makes as “innovation for better existence” (IFBE).Footnote 38Furthermore, moving towards the peak of the triangle and hence limiting the type of innovation that SE seeks to “social innovation” we move towards convergence, unanimity and paradigm formation and moving in the opposite direction, counter move towards the base, makes divergent ideas, perplexity and residence in a pre-paradigmatic phase.
III. Falsification of “transformative social change”
If there were no innovation (I), there were no entrepreneurship(E), also if there were no innovation, there were no transformative change (TC), accordingly lack of social innovation (SI) is corollary to non-existence of SE, i.e. lack of social innovation means lack of social change (SC) which inherently leads to lack of SE.
IV. Falsification of “recognition of social value-creating opportunities”
“Value-creativity” was excluded in the verification; therefore we discuss falsifiability of “recognition of social opportunities”. Thus, we put forward the following logic:
The prerequisite of any social innovation is taking advantage of social opportunities, i.e. lack of social opportunities (SO) leads to the nonexistence of social innovation (SI) which makes SE. Therefore, social innovation takes place within the recognized, perceived and used social opportunity.
V. Falsification of “not to be sector-bound”
ᅟ
If lack of social innovation (SI) leads to the lack of SE, then lack of social innovation in any sector (public, private, for-profit & not-for-profit) leads to the lack of SE in that sector.
\( \frac{\neg SI\to \neg SE}{\begin{array}{l}\neg SI\wedge PUB.S\to \neg PUB.S. SE\\ {}\neg SI\wedge PRI.S\to \neg PRI.S. SE\\ {}\neg SI\wedge FP.S\to \neg FP.S. SE\\ {}\neg SI\wedge NFP.S\to \neg NFP.S. SE\end{array}} \)
VI. Falsification of “to be creative”
Some authors (Albrecht and Albrecht 1987; Okpara 2007) believe “creativity” entails an abstract form (idea) and; in contrary, “innovation” entails the concrete form (practice) (i.e. creativity is conceptual and innovation is practical since innovation is the creativity which has been put into practice).
Therefore we can claim:
Social creativity (SC) Footnote 39 is the prerequisite to social innovation (SI), Footnote 40 since innovation is the conceptual creative idea which was put into practice and the final result is SE. Footnote 41 Therefore in the absence of social creativity, there is no social innovation and consequently no SE.
On the other hand, in management literature “creativity” and “innovation” are mostly discussed simultaneously (e.g. Amabile 1988; Marković et al. 2012; Martins and Terblanche 2003; Ekvall 1996; Luecke and Katz 2003; Robinson and Stern 1998; Bassett-Jones 2005; McLean 2005; Heunks 1998; DiLiello and Houghton 2006; Somech and Drach-Zahavy 2013).Therefore, even if they happen together and there would not be a priority or posteriority, we can assert the following logic:
Innovation (I) and creativity (C) are interrelated
I ↔ C
Accordingly, social innovation (SI) is interrelated to social creativity (SC), and since one of the possible ways which leads to social innovation is SE, then we can claim that SE is also requires social creativity, and hence it is an accepted SE definitional component:
\( \frac{I\leftrightarrow C}{SI\leftrightarrow SC} \)
In other words, lack of social innovation (SI) and social creativity (SC) are simultaneous which inherently leads to lack of SE:
Therefore, the following SE definitional components successfully pass falsifiability:
-
1.
“social mission”
-
2.
“social innovation”
-
3.
“transformative social change”
-
4.
“recognition of social opportunities”
-
5.
“not to be sector-bound”
-
6.
“to be creative”
Table 6 has summarized the final SE definitional components in relation to internalist (P1), externalist (P2), verificationist (P3) and falsificationist (P4) propositions.
Conclusion
Different scholars magnify different definitional components which lead to perplexity and ambiguity. It is noteworthy that abundance of various “epistemic values”Footnote 42and scientific cognitions in any knowledge is not inherently unfavorable since it potentially intensifies the debates among the scholars in any field of social sciences and act as a catalyst toward the formation of a true and comprehensive paradigm; but in the case of SE definition because of its residence in a pre-paradigmatic stage, mostly will act as a disparity making tool instead of an enriching one. Empiricism and its orientation Logical Positivism which was applied in this paper as the research paradigm, is only beneficial in the early stages of consensus-making process among the SE scholars, but as SE develops and evolves through its paradigmatic voyage, Logical Positivism will be strict and dull and in order to be able to reveal SE holistically the necessity of other schools of thought such as Constructivism, Discourse Analysis, Phenomenology, etc. would become evident. The paper’s authors used this approach as a starting point for a unanimous definition of SE and as an early stage of paradigm-making process in SE and do not believe it is a sufficient tool for the subsequent stages of SE paradigm-making process. The justification behind the use of logic in this paper through Verificationism and Falsificationism was presenting “scientifically meaningful” statements by Verificationism and reverse logic in our justifications by the other. Finally, by showing the logical interrelationship between the constituents of generalized definitional components of SE, which are also supported by the SE literature, and presenting logical justifications for each one, the paper’s suggestion for a more consensus-based and epistemologically-supported definition for SE is presented in the following:
“Social entrepreneurship is a socially mission-oriented innovation which seeks beneficial transformative social change by creativity and recognition of social opportunities in any sectors.”
Notes
A term coined by Ralf Dahrendorf (1929-2009).
Stagflation: (n) “persistent inflation combined with stagnant consumer demand and relatively high unemployment” (Merriam Webster’s on-line dictionary, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/stagflation).
Although Capitalism still needs SE as much as any other school of political economy, recently an article by David Bornstein in The New York Times (10 Oct. 2017) entitled, “Giving Capitalism a Social Conscience” quotes Muhammad Yunus’ - “the Bangladeshi founder of the Grameen Bank”- view in his most recent book A World of Three Zeros: The New Economics of Zero Poverty, Zero Unemployment, and Zero Net Carbon Emissions, “that capitalism is in crisis and remains moored in a flawed conception of human motivation. He proposes a far more robust role in the economy for ‘social businesses,’ which he defines as ‘non-dividend’ companies ‘dedicated to solving human problems.’”
“Coined by Bill Drayton of Ashoka in the early 1980’s” (Shapiro 2013: Forbes on-line website).
Such a case is also true for SE, since we always approach SE with the knowledge we have about entrepreneurship.
S and p, stand for Subject and Proposition respectively.
“The study and measurement of interpersonal relationships in a group of people” (Merriam Webster on-line dictionary).
Although the words Substructure and Superstructure are loaned from Marx, his interpretation is not expected here.
Snowball Effect
Pragmatism “emphasizes the practical application of ideas by acting on them to actually test them in human experiences”. (Gutek 2014)
“In logic and probability theory, two propositions (or events) are mutually exclusive or disjoint if they cannot both be true (occur). A clear example is the set of outcomes of a single coin toss, which can result in either heads or tails, but not both.” (Wikipedia)
Borrowed from Albert Einstein’s “A man should look for what is, and not for what he thinks should be.”
“Implicit bias is a term of art referring to relatively unconscious and relatively automatic features of prejudiced judgment and social behavior.” (Brownstein 2015).
Plato believed the objects are reflecting to us in this world the same as shadows, we are entrapped as prisoners in a cave and only we can see the shadows of the objects on the wall of the cave because of a fire out of the cave but we should try to get to the perfect form of the real things by leaving the cave.
Dees (1998b) did not call his definition as “pentagonal”; such an attribution is given to his definition by the authors of the paper since he mentioned five factors as the definitional components of social entrepreneurs and accordingly SE.
“According to Evidentialism, what makes a belief justified … is the possession of evidence. The basic idea is that a belief is justified to the degree it fits S’s evidence” (Steup, 2016).
The other definitional components that Dees(1998b) mentioned for social entrepreneurs but also applicable to SE are as the following:
1.Recognizing and relentlessly pursuing new opportunities to serve that mission,
2.Engaging in a process of continuous innovation, adaptation, and learning,
3.Acting boldly without being limited by resources currently in hand, and
4. Exhibiting a heightened sense of accountability to the constituencies served and for the outcomes created.
“Social mission statement” is necessary but not sufficient. An SEO must also have “social vision statement”; otherwise the organization is not strategically an SEO, but a sporadic practitioner of SE.
Non-SEOs do not have a social mission statement, therefore even though some of them in some cases show Corporate Social Responsibility (CSR), it could not be counted as SE, because usually either their social philanthropy is for a short term or it is for some reasons as acquiring a good reputation for the company.
According to Logical Propositions’ rules:
Schumpeterian “creative destruction” is in essence a change.
Note: Dees (1998b) was not applied the term “economic utility” directly. “Utility is a term used by economists to describe the measurement of ‘useful-ness’ that a consumer obtains from any good” (Wikibooks).
It also shows Contextualism which is discussed previously (Because authors usually attribute different types of “knows” to the concept of “value-creation”).
Environmental Entrepreneurship
On condition that we take the “hard” meaning of the word “social”.
Note: In this paper for all our discussions we have taken the hard meaning of the word “social” in the phrase “social entrepreneurship” (i.e. the word “social” only refers to society; thus the ecological and environmental concepts are specified to Ecopreneurship and Green Entrepreneurship, respectively).
A priori
A posteriori
Corollary
“Epistemic value is a kind of value which attaches to cognitive successes such as true beliefs, justified beliefs, knowledge, and understanding” (Bondy 2017).
References
Abu-Saifan, S. (2012). Social entrepreneurship: Definition and boundaries. Technology Innovation Management Review, 2(2), 22–27.
Ahlden, Y. (2016). Three challenges in defining social enterprises, 29 Nov. https://avpn.asia/blog/three-challenges-in-defining-social-enterprises/ . Accessed 14 Dec. 2017.
Albrecht, K, & Albrecht, SW (1987). The creative corporation. New York: McGraw-Hill Professional Book Group.
Alterowitz, R (1988). New corporate ventures. New York: Wiley.
Alvord, SH, Brown, LD, Letts, CW. (2004). Social entrepreneurship and societal transformation: An exploratory study. The Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 40(3), 260–282.
Amabile, TM. (1988). A model of creativity and innovation in organizations. Research in Organizational Behavior, 10(1), 123–167.
Amabile, TM. (1997). Entrepreneurial creativity through motivational synergy. Journal of Creative Behavior, 31(1), 18–26.
Anderson, BB, & Dees, JG (2002). Developing viable earned income strategies. In JG Dees, J Emerson, P Economy (Eds.), Strategic tools for social entrepreneurs: Enhancing the performance of your enterprising nonprofit. New York: Wiley.
Ashmore, M. (1991). Review of “reflexive epistemology: the philosophical legacy of Otto Neurath” by D. Zolo & D. McKie. Isis, 82(4), (pp.787–788), The University of Chicago Press on behalf of The History of Science Society. http://www.jstor.org/stable/233405. Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Audi, R (1988). Belief, justification and knowledge. California: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Audi, R (2010). Objective-subjective. In J Dancy, E Sosa, M Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology, (2nd ed., p. 558). New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Austin, J, Stevenson, H, Wei-Skillern, J. (2006). Social and commercial entrepreneurship: Same, different, or both? Entrepreneurship: Theory & Practice, 30(1), 1–22.
Bacq, S, & Janssen, F. (2011). The multiple faces of social entrepreneurship: A review of definitional issues based on geographical and thematic criteria. Entrepreneurship & Regional Development, 23(5-6), 373–403 http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/08985626.2011.577242 . Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Baron, DP. (2007). Corporate social responsibility and social entrepreneurship. Journal of Economics & Management Strategy, 16(3), 683–717.
Bassett-Jones, N. (2005). The paradox of diversity management, creativity and innovation. Creativity and Innovation Management, 14(2), 169–175.
Battilana, J, Lee, M, Walker, J, Dorsey, C. (2012). In search of the hybrid ideal. Stanford Social Innovation Review summer. https://ssir.org/articles/entry/in_search_of_the_hybrid_ideal. Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Berthon, P, McHulbert, J, Pitt, L. (2004). Innovation or customer orientation? An empirical investigation. European Journal of Marketing, 38(9/10), 1065–1090.
Blanding, M (2013). Entrepreneurs and the “hybrid” organization, Aug. 12 th. Forbes https://www.forbes.com/sites/hbsworkingknowledge/2013/08/12/entrepreneurs-and-the-hybrid-organization/#52fdc4fa62ae. Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Bondy, P. (2017). Epistemic value. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/ep-value/ . Accessed 18 Oct 2017.
Bonjour, L (2008). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. In E Sosa, J Kim, J Fantl, M McGrath (Eds.), Epistemology, (p. 365). Malden: Blackwell.
Bonjour, L (2010). Recent work on the internalism–externalism controversy. In J Dancy, E Sosa, M Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology, (2nd ed., pp. 31–43). New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Bornstein, D. (2012). The rise of the social entrepreneur, 13 Nov. 2012. https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2012/11/13/the-rise-of-social-entrepreneur/. Accessed 25 Dec 2017.
Bornstein, D. (2017). Giving capitalism a social conscience, The New York Times, 10 Oct. https://www.nytimes.com/2017/10/10/opinion/giving-capitalism-a-social-conscience.html. Accessed 25 Dec 2017.
Boyatzis, R (1998). Transforming qualitative information: Themaitc analysis and code development. Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Brooks, AC (2009). Social entrepreneurship: A modern approach to social venture creation. Upper Saddle River: Pearson International Edition.
Brouard, F., Hebb, T., & Madill, J. (2008). Development of a social enterprise typology in a Canadian context. https://carleton.ca/3ci/wp-content/uploads/SETypologyPaper2.pdf . Accessed 18 Oct 2017.
Brownstein, M (2015). Implicit bias. In EN Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/implicit-bias/#Epi. Accessed 21 Oct 2017.
Bugg-Levine, A, Kogut, B, Kulatilaka, N. (2012). Unbundling societal benefits and financial returns can dramatically increase investment. Harvard Business Review, 120–122.
Burgelman, RA. (1984). Designs for corporate entrepreneurship. California Management Review, 26, 154–166.
Catania L. M. (2012). Corporate branding of social entrepreneurial ventures: A method to overcome social entrepreneurs’ challenges of managing multiple identities, resource mobilization and heterogeneous networks of stakeholders? Master thesis, Maastricht University. No. I6014208.
Certo, ST, & Miller, T. (2008). Social entrepreneurship: Key issues and concepts. Business Horizons, 51(4), 267–271.
Choi, D, & Gray, E. (2008). The venture development processes of “sustainable” entrepreneurs. Management Research News, 8(31), 558–569.
Christiansen, C (1997). The innovators’ dilemma. Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press.
Christie, M, & Honig, B. (2006). Social entrepreneurship: New research findings. Journal of World Business, 41(1), 1–5.
Christlieb, J (2012). Measuring social value creation: A quantitative study among social entrepreneurs, Master thesis (). Berlin: Technische Universität.
Cohen, B, & Winn, M. (2007). Market imperfections, opportunity and sustainable entrepreneurship. Journal of Business Venturing, 22(1), 29–49.
Conee, E, & Feldman, R (2004). Internalism defended. In H Kornblith (Ed.), Epistemology: Internalism and externalism, (pp. 55–56). Oxford: Blackwell.
Corbett, A. (2016). Social entrepreneurship as a norm? Journal of Management Studies, 53, 608–609. https://doi.org/10.1111/joms.12204.
Cornelius, N, Todres, M, Janjuha-Jivraj, S, Woods, A, Wallace, J. (2008). Corporate social responsibility and the social enterprise. Journal of Business Ethics, 81(2), 355–370.
Covin, JG, & Miles, MP. (1999). Corporate entrepreneurship and the pursuit of competitive advantage. Entrepreneurship Theory Practice, 23(3), 47–64.
Covin, JG, & Slevin, DP. (1991). A conceptual model of entrepreneurship as firm behavior. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 16(1), 7–25.
Crisan, CM, & Borza, A. (2012). Social entrepreneurship and corporate social responsibilities. International Business Research, 5(2), 106.
Cukier, W, Trenholm, S, Carl, D, Gekas, G. (2011). Social entrepreneurship: A content analysis. Journal of Strategic Innovation and Sustainability, 7(1), 99–119.
Dacin, MT, Dacin, PA, Tracey, P. (2011). Social entrepreneurship: a critique and future directions. Organization Science, 22(5), 1203–1213.
Dacin, PA, Dacin, MT, Matear, M. (2010). Social entrepreneurship: Why we don’t need a new theory and how we move forward from here. Academy of Management Perspectives, 24(3), 37–58.
Dees, JG (1998a). Enterprising nonprofits: What do you do when traditional sources of funding fall short? Harvard Business Review, January/February, (pp. 55–67).
Dees, J. G. (1998b). The meaning of social entrepreneurship, (2001 Revision). https://entrepreneurship.duke.edu/news-item/the-meaning-of-social-entrepreneurship/ . Accessed 14 Oct. 2017.
Dees, JG, & Anderson, B (2006). Rhetoric, reality, and research: Building a solid foundation for the practice of social entrepreneurship. In A Nicholls (Ed.), Social entrepreneurship: New models of sustainable social change, (pp. 144–168). Oxford: Oxford University.
DiLiello, TC, & Houghton, JD. (2006). Maximizing organizational leadership capacity for the future: Toward a model of self-leadership, innovation and creativity. Journal of Managerial Psychology, 21(4), 319–337.
Dixon, W, & Wilson, D (2013). A history of Homo Economicus: The nature of the moral in economic theory. New York: Routledge.
Drayton, W. (2002). The citizen sector: Becoming as entrepreneurial and competitive as business. California Management Review, 44(3), 120–132.
Drucker, PF (1985). Innovation and entrepreneurship. New York: Harper & Row Publishers.
Ekvall, G. (1996). Organizational climate for creativity and innovation. European Journal of Work and Organizational Psychology, 5(1), 105–123.
Emerson, J. (2003). The blended value proposition: Integrating social and financial returns. California Management Review, 45(4), 35–51.
Emerson, J, & Twersky, F (1996). New social entrepreneurs: The success, challenge and lessons of non-profit enterprise creation. San Francisco: The Roberts Foundation, Homeless Economic Development Fund September.
Eppler, I. (2012).The problem with “social entrepreneurship”: A student’s perspective, 13 Apr. https://ssir.org/articles/entry/the_problem_with_social_entrepreneurship_a_students_perspective. Accessed 25 Dec. 2017.
Feldman, R (2010). Contextualism. In J Dancy, E Sosa, M Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology, (2nd ed., pp. 3–11). New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Ferreira, J. (2002). Corporate entrepreneurship: A strategic and structural perspective. International Council for Small Business 47th World Conference, San Juan, Puerto Rico, June 16–19.
Forbes. (2016).5 reasons why social entrepreneurship is the new business model, 8 Aug. https://www.forbes.com/sites/meimeifox/2016/08/08/5-reasons-why-social-entrepreneurship-is-the-new-business-model/#634c40a444ca. Accessed 25 Dec. 2017.
Fowler, A. (2000). NGDOs as a moment in history: Beyond aid to social entrepreneurship or civic innovation? Third World Quarterly, 21(4), 637–654.
Frank, RH. (1987). If homo economicus could choose his own utility function, would he want one with a conscience? The American Economic Review, 77(4), 593–604.
Frum, D (2000). How we got Here: The 70's. New York: Basic Books.
Galindo, MA, & Mendez, MT. (2008). Emprendedores objectovos de politica economica. informacion comercial espanola, March-April, 841, 29–40.
Gilad, B. (1984). Entrepreneurship: The issue of creativity in the market place. Journal of Creative Behavior, 18(3), 151–161.
Global Entrepreneurship Monitor. (2009). 2009 report on social entrepreneurship, prepared by Siri Terjesen; Jan Lepoutre; Rachida Justo; and Niels Bosma. http://www.gemconsortium.org/report/48437. Accessed 25 Dec. 2017.
Global Entrepreneurship Monitor. (2016). Social topic report: Social entrepreneurship, prepared by Niels Bosma; Thomas Schøtt; Siri Terjesen; and penny Kew. http://gemconsortium.org/report/49542. Accessed 25 Dec. 2017.
Goldman, A. (1999). Internalism exposed. The Journal of Philosophy, 96, 271–293.
Goldman, A (2010). Relaibilism. In J Dancy, E Sosa, M Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology, (2nd ed., pp. 681–691). New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Granados, ML, Hlupic, V, Coakes, E, Mohamed, S. (2011). Social enterprise and social entrepreneurship research and theory: A bibliometric analysis from 1991 to 2010. Social Enterprise Journal, 7(3), 198–218.
Gutek, G (2014). Philosophical, ideological, and theoretical perspectives on education. New Jersey: Pearson.
Haigh, N, & Hoffman, A. (2012). Hybrid organizations: The next chapter of sustainable business. Organizational Dynamics, 41, 126–134.
Harding, R. (2004). Social enterprise: The new economic engine? Business Strategy Review, 15(4), 39–43.
Herbert, RF, & Link, AN. (1989). In search of the meaning of entrepreneurship. Small Business Economics, 1, 39–49.
Heunks, FJ. (1998). Innovation, creativity and success. Small Business Economics, 10(3), 263–272.
Hibbert, SA, Hogg, G, Quinn, T. (2002). Consumer response to social entrepreneurship: The case of the big issue in Scotland. International Journal of Non-profit and Voluntary Sector Marketing, 7(3), 288–301.
Hibbert, SA, Hogg, G, Quinn, T. (2005). Social entrepreneurship: Understanding consumer motives for buying the big issue. Journal of Consumer Behaviour, 4(3), 159–172.
Hirsch, PM, & Levin, DZ. (1999). Umbrella advocates versus validity police: A life-cycle model. Organizational Science, 10(2), 199–212.
Hlady-Rispal, M, & Servantie, V. (2016). Deconstructing the way in which value is created in the context of social entrepreneurship. International Journal of Management Reviews. https://doi.org/10.1111/ijmr.12113.
Hoffman, A. J., Badiane, K. K., & Haigh, N. (2010). Hybrid organizations as agents of positive social change: Bridging the for-profit & non-profit divide, Ross School of business, working paper. http://ssrn.com/abstract=1675069 . Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Hoogendoorn, B. (2011). Social entrepreneurship in the modern economy: Warm glow, cold feet. Doctoral thesis, Erasmus University Rotterdam, ERIM reference number: EPS-2011 246 STR, ISBN 978-90-5892-289-2 .
Hoogendoorn, B, Pennings, E, Thurik, AR. (2010). What do we know about social entrepreneurship: An analysis of empirical research. International Review of Entrepreneurship, 8(2), 71–112.
Isenberg, DJ. (2010). How to start an entrepreneurial revolution. Harvard Business Review, 88(6), 40–50.
Johnson, P, & Duberley, J (2000). Understanding management research: An introduction to epistemology. Sage.
Johnson, S (2000). Literature review on social entrepreneurship. Canadian Centre for Social Entrepreneurship. Canada: University of Alberta.
Kanter, RM. (1985). Supporting innovation and venture development in established companies. Journal of Business Venturing, 1, 47–60.
Kerlin, JA. (2006). Social enterprise in the United States and abroad: Learning from our differences. ARNOVA Occasional Paper Series: Research on Social Entrepreneurship: Understanding and Contributing to an Emerging Field, 1(3), 105–125.
Kuratko, DF, & Hodgetts, RM (1995). Entrepreneurship: A contemporary approach, (3rd ed., ). Orlando: Dryden Press.
Lapowsky, I.(2011). The social entrepreneurship spectrum : For-profit with a social mission. Inc. Magazine, May Issue. https://www.inc.com/magazine/20110501/the-social-entrepreneurship-spectrum-for-profit-with-a-social-mission.html . Accessed 14 Oct. 2017.
Lasprogata, GA, & Cotton, MN. (2003). Contemplating enterprise: The business and legal challenges of social entrepreneurship. American Business Law Journal, 41(1), 67.
Leimsider, R.(2014). 5 bad reasons to start a for-profit enterprise. Harvard Business Review, July 30th. https://hbr.org/2014/07/5-bad-reasons-to-start-a-for-profit-social-enterprise . Accessed 14 Oct. 2017.
Lessnoff, M (1974). The structure of social science: A philosophical introduction. London: Allen and Unwin.
Luecke, R, & Katz, R (2003). Harvard business essentials: Managing creativity and innovation. Harvard Business School Press.
Lumpkin, GT, & Dess, GG. (1996). Clarifying the entrepreneurial orientation construct and linking it to performance. The Academy of Management Review, and, 21(1), 135–172.
Mair, J, & Marti, I. (2006). Social entrepreneurship research: A source of explanation, prediction and delight. Journal of World Business, 41(1), 36–44.
Markie, P (2010). The power of perception. In J Dancy, E Sosa, M Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology, (2nd ed., p. 72). New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Marković, J, Prodanović, R, Mutibarić, J. (2012). Creativity and innovation in entrepreneurship. Ekonomija, 5(3), 47–59.
Martin, R.L. & Osberg, S. (2007). Social entrepreneurship: The case for definition. Stanford school innovation review. https://ssir.org/articles/entry/social_entrepreneurship_the_case_for_definition . Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Martins, EC, & Terblanche, F. (2003). Building organisational culture that stimulates creativity and innovation. European Journal of Innovation Management, 6(1), 64–74.
McLean, LD. (2005). Organizational culture’s influence on creativity and innovation: A review of the literature and implications for human resource development. Advances in Developing Human Resources, 7(2), 226–246.
Miles, RE, & Snow, CC. (1978). Organizations new concepts for new forms. California Management Review, 18, 62–73.
Miller, D, & Friesen, PH. (1982). Innovation in conservative and entrepreneurial firms: Two models of strategic momentum. Strategic Management Journal, 3(1), 1–25.
Miller, DT (2014). Sarah Soule: How activism can fuel corporate social responsibility. Stanford Business 10 Oct. https://www.gsb.stanford.edu/insights/sarah-soule-how-activism-can-fuel-corporate-social-responsibility. Accessed 25 Dec 2017.
Mohd Osman, MH, Rashid, MA, Ahmad, FS, Hussain, G. (2011). Entrepreneurial orientation: An overview of theory and insinuations for women owned smbs to model business performance in developing countries. Interdisciplinary Journal of Contemporary Research in Business, 3(3), 329–340.
Morris, MH, & Kuratko, DF (2002). Corporate entrepreneurship. Mason: South-Western College Publishers.
Mort, G, Weerawardena, J, Carnegie, K. (2002). Social entrepreneurship: Towards conceptualization. International Journal of Non-profit and Voluntary Sector Marketing, 8(1), 76–88.
Naman, JL, & Slevin, DP. (1993). Entrepreneurship and the concept of fit: A model and empirical tests. Strategic Management Journal, 14, 137–154.
Neurath, O (1944). Foundations of the social sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Newbert, SL. (2014). Editorial: Building theory in social entrepreneurship. Journal of Social Entrepreneurship, 5(3), 239–242.
Nicholls, A (Ed.) (2006). Social entrepreneurship: New models of sustainable social change. USA: Oxford University Press.
Nicholls, A (2009). Learning to walk: Social entrepreneurship – A research review. Innovations: Special Edition, Social Entrepreneurship, (pp. 209–222).
Nicholls, A. (2010). The legitimacy of social entrepreneurship: Reflexive isomorphism in a pre-paradigmatic field. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 34(4), 611–633.
Nicholls, A, & Cho, A (2006). Social entrepreneurship: The structuration of a field. In A Nicholls (Ed.), Social entrepreneurship: New models of sustainable social change, (pp. 99–118). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nijkamp, P (2000). Entrepreneurship in a modern network economy. In Research memorandum, 42. Amesterdam: Vrije Universitiet.
Nyssens, M (2006). Social enterprise: At the crossroads of markets, public policies and civil society. London: Routledge, Taylor Francis Group.
O’Hear, A. (2010). Popper, Karl. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (2nd ed.). (pp. 597-598). New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Okpara, FO. (2007). The value of creativity and innovation in entrepreneurship. Journal of Asia Entrepreneurship and Sustainability, 3(2), 1.
Pappas, G (2014). Internalist vs. externalist conceptions of epistemic justification. In EN Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (fall 2014 edition) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/justep-intext/ . Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Peredo, AM, & McLean, M. (2006). Social entrepreneurship: A critical review of the concept. Journal of World Business, 41(1), 56–65.
Perrini, F, & Vurro, C (2006). Social entrepreneurship: Innovation and social change across theory and practice. Social entrepreneurship, (pp. 57–85). UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
Picot, S (2012). Jugend in der Zivilgesellschaft – Freiwilliges engagement Jugendlicher im Wandel (young people in civil society – Voluntary engagement in the process of change). Gütersloh: Verlag Bertelsmann Stiftung.
Prabhu, GN. (1999). Social entrepreneurship leadership. Career Development International, 4(3), 140–145.
Psillos, S, & Curd, M (2010). The Routledge companion to philosophy of science, (pp. 129–138). London: Routledge.
Rao, V. (2012). Report by the credit Suisse research institute: How social entrepreneurship is redefining the meaning of return. https://yourstory.com/2012/02/report-by-the-credit-suisse-research-institute-how-social-entrepreneurship-is-redefining-the-meaning-of-return/. Accessed 25 Dec 2017.
Reis, TK, & Clohesy, SJ. (2001). Unleashing new resources and entrepreneurship for the common good: A philanthropic renaissance. New Directions for Philanthropic Fundraising, Summer, 32, 109–143.
Roberts, D, & Woods, C. (2005). Changing the world on a shoestring: The concept of social entrepreneurship. Business Review, 7(1), 45–51.
Robinson, A, & Stern, S (1998). Corporate creativity: How innovation and improvement actually happen. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Publishers, Inc.
Rowshan, SA, & Forouharfar, A. (2014). Customized social entrepreneurship theory & customized social entrepreneurship strategy as a theory conceptualization & practice towards sustainable development in Iran. Asian Journal of Research in Social Sciences and Humanities, 4(8), 367–385.
Rwigema, H, & Venter, R (2004). Advanced entrepreneurship. Cape Town: Oxford University Press.
Salarzehi, H, & Forouharfar, A. (2011). Understanding barriers to intrapreneurship in work and social affairs governmental organization: A case study in Iran. Interdisciplinary Journal of Contemporary Research in Business, 2(12), 490–503.
Santos, FM. (2012). A positive theory of social entrepreneurship. Journal of Business Ethics, 111(3), 335–351.
Sarasvathy, S. D., & Wicks, A. C. (2003). Value creation through entrepreneurship: Reconciling the two meanings of the good life. Under revision by Academy of Management Review.
Sassmannshausen, SP, & Volkmann, C (2013). A bibliometric based review on social entrepreneurship and its establishment as a field of research. In Schumpeter discussion papers 2013-003. Germany: University of Wuppertal.
Scheuerle, T, Schües, R, Richter, S (2013). Mapping social entrepreneurship in Germany: A quantitative analysis. Centre for Social Investment: University of Heidelberg.
Schumpeter, JA (1951). In RV Clemence (Ed.), Essays: On entrepreneurs, innovations, business cycles, and the evolution of capitalism. Cambridge: Addison-Wesley.
Seelos, C, & Mair, J. (2005). Social entrepreneurship: Creating new business models to serve the poor. Business Horizons, 48(3), 241–246.
Sekliuckiene, J, & Kisielius, E. (2015). Development of social entrepreneurship initiatives: A theoretical framework, 20th international scientific conference economics and management (ICEM-2015). Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences, 213, 1015–1019.
Shapiro, R (2013). Social entrepreneurship: A fundamental game changer. Forbes 7 Jan. https://www.forbes.com/sites/skollworldforum/2013/01/07/social-entrepreneurship-a-fundamental-game-changer/#76a3b1c5553f. Accessed 25 Dec. 2017.
Shaw, E. (2004). Marketing in the social enterprise context: Is it entrepreneurial? Qualitative Market Research: An International Journal, 7(3), 194–205.
Sheldon, PJ, & Daniele, R (2017). Social entrepreneurship and tourism: Philosophy and practice. Springer International Publishing. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-46518-0.
Short, JC, Moss, TW, Lumpkin, GT. (2009). Research in social entrepreneurship: Past contributions and future opportunities. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 3(2), 161–194.
Simon, HA (1996). The architecture of complexity, the sciences of the artificial. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Slater, SF, & Narver, JC. (2000). Intelligence generation and superior customer value. Journal of the Academy of Marketing Science, 28(1), 120–127.
Smart, DT, & Conant, JS. (1994). Entrepreneurial orientation, distinctive marketing competencies and organizational performance. Journal of Applied Business Research, 10(3), 18–28.
Somech, A, & Drach-Zahavy, A. (2013). Translating team creativity to innovation implementation: The role of team composition and climate for innovation. Journal of Management, 39(3), 684–708.
Sosa, E, Kim, J, Fantl, J, McGrath, M (2008). Introduction to part V. In E Sosa, J Kim, J Fantl, M McGrath (Eds.), Epistemology, (pp. 305–309). Malden: Blackwell.
Stam, FC, & Spigel, B. (2016). Entrepreneurial ecosystems. USE Discussion paper series, 16(13) https://www.uu.nl/en/file/55729/download?token=dzRMYt-t. Accessed 14 Dec 2017.
Steup, M (2016). In EN Zalta (Ed.), Epistemology, The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/epistemology/ . Accessed 14 Oct 2017.
Stevenson, HH, Roberts, MJ, Grousbeck, HL (1989). New business ventures and the entrepreneur. Homewood: Irwin.
Stryjan, Y (2006). The practice of social entrepreneurship: Notes toward a resource perspective. In C Steyaert, D Hjorth (Eds.), Entrepreneurship as social change: A third movements in entrepreneurship book, (pp. 35–55). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.
Subrt, J (2017). The perspective of historical sociology: The individual as Homo-Sociologicus through society and history. UK: Emerald Publishing.
Szegedi, K, Fülöp, G, Bereczk, Á. (2016). Relationships between social entrepreneurship, CSR and social innovation: In theory and practice. World Academy of Science, Engineering and Technology, International Journal of Social, Behavioral, Educational, Economic, Business and Industrial Engineering, 10(5), 1534–1539.
Tafel, R. (2011) Social entrepreneurs must achieve not survive, Stanford Social Innovation Review, 15 Sep. https://ssir.org/articles/entry/social_entrepreneurs_must_achieve_not_survive. Accessed 25 Dec. 2017.
Tan, NT. (2004). Social entrepreneurship: Challenge for social work in a changing world. Asia Pacific Journal of Social Work and Development, 14(2), 87–98 https://doi.org/10.1080/21650993.2004.9755956 . Accessed 20 Dec. 2017.
Tan, W, Williams, J, Tan, T. (2005). Defining the “social” in “social entrepreneurship”: Altruism and entrepreneurship. International Entrepreneurship and Management Journal, 1(3), 353–365.
Thake, S, & Zadek, S (1997). Practical people, noble causes: How to support community-based social entrepreneurs. London: New Economics Foundation.
The Economist. (2006). The rise of the social entrepreneur, 23 Feb. http://www.economist.com/node/5517666. Accessed 14 Dec 2017.
Thornton, S (2017). Karl Popper. In EN Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy https://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=popper. Accessed 21 Oct 2017.
Timmons, JA. (1978). Characteristics and role demands of entrepreneurship. American Journal of Small Business, 3(1), 5–17.
Timmons, JA, & Spinelli, S (2003). New venture creation: Entrepreneurship for the 21 st century. Boston: McGraw- Hill.
Townsend, DM, & Hart, TA (2008). Perceived institutional ambiguity and the choice of organizational form in social entrepreneurial ventures. Baylor University http://ssrn.com/abstract=1313848. Accessed 14 Oct. 2017.
Tracey, P, & Jarvis, O. (2007). Toward a theory of social venture franchising. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 31(5), 667–685.
Tran, T. (2015). Corporate social responsibility and profits: A tradeoff or a balance?. Center on democracy, development, and the rule of law at Stanford University. http://cddrl.fsi.stanford.edu/sites/default/files/thuy_tran_cddrl_thesis_v3.pdf. Accessed 14 Dec 2017.
Ussahawanitchakit, P. (2007). The influences of management capability on export performance of leather businesses in Thailand. Review of Business Research, 7(5), 1–10.
Van Praag, CM. (1999). Some classic views on entrepreneurship. De Economist, 147(3), 311–335.
Waddock, S, & Post, JE. (1991). Social entrepreneurs and catalytic change. Public Administration Review, 51(5), 393–401.
Ward, TB. (2004). Cognition, creativity, and entrepreneurship. Journal of Business Venturing, 19(2), 173–188.
Weerawardena, J, & Mort, GS. (2006). Investigating social entrepreneurship: A multidimensional model. Journal of World Business, 41(1), 21–35.
Weisbrod, BA (1977). The voluntary nonprofit sector. Lexington: Lexington Books.
Whiting, BG. (1988). Creativity and entrepreneurship: How do they relate? Journal of Creative Behavior, 22(3), 178–183.
Wikibooks, Principles of economics /Utility.https://en.wikibooks.org/wiki/Principles_of_Economics/Utility. Accessed 21 Oct. 2017.
Wikipedia. Mutual exclusivity.https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mutual_exclusivity. Accessed 21 Oct 2017.
Yujuico, E. (2008). Connecting the dots in social entrepreneurship through the capabilities approach. Socio-Economy Review, 6, 493–513.
Yunus, M (2008). Creating a world without poverty: Social business and the future of capitalism. New York: Public Affairs Books.
Zahra, SA, & Covin, JG. (1995). Contextual influences on the corporate entrepreneurship–performance relationship: A longitudinal analysis. Journal of Business Venturing, 10, 43–58.
Zahra, SA, Gedajlovic, E, Neubaum, DO, Shulman, JM. (2009). A typology of social entrepreneurs: Motives, search processes and ethical challenges. Journal of Business Venturing, 24(5), 519–532.
Zahra, SA, & Wright, M. (2016). Rethinking the social role of entrepreneurship. Journal of Management Studies, 53, 610–629.
Zakić, N, Jovanović, A, Stamatović, M. (2008). External and internal factors affecting the product and business innovation. Economics and Organization, 5(1), 17–29.
Zeyen, A (2014). Scaling strategies of social entrepreneurship organizations– an actor-motivation perspective. Doctoral thesis. Germany: Leuphana University Lueneburg.
Acknowledgements
The authors like to show their hearty gratitude to the scholarly comments of two anonymous scholars who dedicated their precious time to read the first draft of the paper.
This paper is adopted from the unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation of Amir Forouharfar entitled “Social Entrepreneurship Model Designing and Strategy Setting for the Sustainable Development of Iran.”
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
All authors contributed equally and they read and approved the final manuscript.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Competing interests
The authors declare that they have no competing interests.
Publisher’s Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made.
About this article
Cite this article
Forouharfar, A., Rowshan, S.A. & Salarzehi, H. An epistemological critique of social entrepreneurship definitions. J Glob Entrepr Res 8, 11 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1186/s40497-018-0098-2
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s40497-018-0098-2