Skip to main content
Log in

Geniuses, exiles and (liberal) postmodern subjectivities

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal of International Relations and Development Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article argues that Ashley and Walker's ‘dissident exile’ and Mill's ‘genius’ are virtual mirror images of one another due to the fact that both subject formulations rely on the concept of individual autonomy. Postmodern iterations of subjectivity such as those found in the work of Ashley and Walker place a great deal of emphasis on alterity and ethical engagement, striving to move beyond the ethical limitations of Enlightenment liberalism that valorises the atomised, sovereign individual. But both Mill's genius, who can choose his or her own mode of existence or plan of life, and Ashley and Walker's dissident exile, who engages in self-making in a register of freedom, are inextricably bound up with and reliant upon one of liberalism's seminal concepts: autonomy. The implications of this in terms of theorising new forms of subjectivity in international relations are significant because replacing autonomy with heteronomy or recasting autonomy in relational terms fails to fully acknowledge how central autonomy is to the entire project of critique. The critical attitude that Ashley and Walker, as well as Mill, exhibit emanates from within Enlightenment liberalism; since the very act of critique rests on the exercise of individual autonomy, perhaps the most we can hope for in terms of new iterations of subjectivity may only be one that is more expansively ‘liberal’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In an effort to draw attention to critical theory's unfulfilled potential and promise, Jahn (1998: 614) eschews ‘critical theory’ as little more than a ‘reenactment of liberal idealism’ and ‘reminiscent of an “imperialistic project” ’. I am indebted to her for opening critical pathways for my own examination of postmodernism.

  2. Blaney (1996: 473) provides such a nuanced reading of autonomy in his call for a more relational understanding of autonomy, which offers ‘a conception of national autonomy within social relationships, endorsing a vision of the pursuit of local ways of life and global projects by every people or state within an interdependent and more egalitarian global society’. The key is to retain the individual capacity of communities to be self-determining and self-realising, thus strengthening their ability to critique global patterns of economic inequality.

  3. In a slightly different vein, Burke (2007: 19) draws upon both the ‘progressive discourses of emancipation and cosmopolitanism’ in order to reimagine human subjectivity disentangled from Foucauldian forms of social and governmental power which can be repositioned around an ‘ethics of responsibility and reciprocity’.

  4. Mill detractors include Cowling (1963), Hamburger (1999), Himmelfarb (1974) and Jahn (2005). However, C.L. Ten (2002, 1980: 173) concludes, ‘it is as the passionate champion of individual liberty that he has been, and generally still is, attacked or admired’, which explains why Ten regards Mill as a great liberal. Also see Geuss (2002: 323), who identifies toleration, human freedom, individualism and limited power as the key components of classical liberalism associated with Mill, Constant and de Tocqueville.

  5. This section is not an attempt to read Foucault back into Mill but merely serves as an analysis of the concerns expressed by Mill with regard to the exercise of individual liberty and how Mill's concerns can be read as a foreshadowing of problematisations much more fully developed by Foucault through his explorations of disciplinarity, governmentality and biopolitics. Foucault and Mill obviously part company over the concept of sovereignty because Foucault regards sovereignty as the key conceptual breakfront in limiting our efforts to imagine other forms of subjectivity.

  6. Comprehensive formulations of liberalism provide ‘detailed theories of human nature and the human good that include controversial moral claims and commitments’ (Paul et al. 2007: viii.). Ryan associates Mill with this strand of liberal thought and thus he argues for an ‘autonomist’ view of liberalism. Such a view rests on the belief that individuals are self-creating, able to evaluate critically their beliefs, design the course of their life, and recognise these same abilities in others (Paul et al. 2007: viii).

  7. See http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/autonomy-moral (accessed 12 June, 2011).

References

  • Apperley, Alan (2000) ‘Liberalism, Autonomy and Stability’, British Journal of Political Science 30 (2): 291–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashley, Richard K. (1989) ‘Living on Border Lines: Man, Poststructuralism, and War’, in James Der Derian and Michael J. Shapiro, eds, International/Intertextual Relations: Postmodern Readings of World Politics, 259–321, New York: Lexington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashley, Richard K. and R.B.J. Walker (1990a) ‘Speaking the Language of Exile: Dissident Thought in International Studies’, International Studies Quarterly 34: 259–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashley, Richard K. and R.B.J. Walker (1990b) ‘Reading Dissidence/Writing the Discipline: Crisis and the Question of Sovereignty in International Studies’, International Studies Quarterly 34: 367–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blaney, David (1996) ‘Reconceptualizing Autonomy: The Difference Dependency Theory Makes’, Review of International Political Economy 3 (3): 459–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blaney, David and Naeem Inayatullah (2000) ‘The Westphalian Deferral’, International Studies Review 2 (2): 29–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blaney, David and Naeem Inayatullah (2004) International Relations and the Problem of Difference, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith (1997) Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative, NewYork: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Anthony (2007) Beyond Security, Ethics and Violence, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, David (1998) ‘Why Fight: Humanitarianism, Principles, and Post-structuralism’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 27 (3): 497–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, David (1993) Politics Without Principle: Sovereignty, Ethics and The Narratives of the Gulf War, Boulder: Lynne Rienner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, David and Michael Shapiro, eds (1999) Moral Spaces, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cochran, Molly (1995) ‘Postmodernism, Ethics and International Political Theory’, Review of International Studies 21: 237–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colburn, Ben (2010) Autonomy and Liberalism, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, William (1991) Identity/Difference: Democratic Negotiations of Political Paradox, New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, William (1995) The Ethos of Pluralization, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowling, Maurice (1963) Mill and Liberalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowder, George (2007) ‘Two Concepts of Liberal Pluralism’, Political Theory 35 (2): 121–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Stefano, Christine (1991) Configurations of Masculinity: A Feminist Perspective on Modern Political Theory, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumm, Thomas (1996) Michel Foucault and the Politics of Freedom, Thousand Oaks: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edkins, Jenny (1999) Poststructuralism and International Relations: Bringing the Political Back In, Boulder: Lynne Rienner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edkins, Jenny (2003) ‘Humanitarianism, Humanity, Human’, Journal of Human Rights 2 (2): 253–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edkins, Jenny and Veronique Pin-Fat (2005) ‘Through the Wire: Relations of Power and Relations of Violence’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 34 (1): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel (1995) Discipline and Punish, New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel (1997) ‘On The Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview of Work in Progress’, in Paul Rabinow, ed., Ethics Subjectivity and Truth, New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, Alan E. (2001) ‘Autonomy, Slavery, and Mill's Critique of Paternalism’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4 (3): 231–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galston, William (2005) The Practice of Liberal Pluralism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, Jim (1994) Discourses of Global Politics: A Critical (Re)Introduction to International Relations, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geuss, Raymond (2002) ‘Liberalism and Its Discontents’, Political Theory 30: 320–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Emily (2010) ‘Geographic Insights into Political Identity’, in Robert Denemark, ed., The International Studies Encyclopedia Vol. V, New York: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, John (1989) Liberalisms: Essays in Political Thought, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, John (1991) ‘Mill's Conception of Happiness and the Theory of Individuality’, in John Gray and G.W. Smith, eds, J.S. Mill's ‘On Liberty’ in Focus, 190–211, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamburger, Joseph (1999) John Stuart Mill on Liberty and Control, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Himmelfarb, Gertrude (1974) On Liberty and Liberalism, New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobhouse, L.T. (1942) Liberalism, London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, Thomas (1987) ‘Why Value Autonomy?’ Social Theory and Practice 13: 361–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, Thomas (1993) Perfectionism, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jabri, Vivienne (1998) ‘Restyling the Subject of Responsibility in International Relations’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 27 (3): 591–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jahn, Beate (1998) ‘One Step Forward, Two Steps Back: Critical Theory as the Latest Edition of Liberal Idealism’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 27 (3): 613–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jahn, Beate (2005) ‘Kant, Mill and Illiberal Legacies in International Affairs’, International Organization 59 (1): 177–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, Sanford (1990) ‘Autonomy and Liberal Democracy’, The Review of Politics 52 (3): 378–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart (1956) On Liberty, New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neufeld, Mark (1995) The Restructuring of International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Orlie, Melissa (1999) ‘Beyond Identity and Difference’, Political Theory 27 (1): 140–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odysseos, Louisa (2007) The Subject of Coexistence: Otherness in International Relations, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, Ellen Frankel, Fred D. Miller and Jeffrey Paul, eds (2007) Liberalism: Old and New, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1971) A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1993) Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph (1978) ‘Principles of Equality’, Mind 87: 321–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph (1986) The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph (1990) ‘Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 19: 3–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenau, Pauline (1992) Post-Modernism and the Social Sciences, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, Alan (2007) ‘Newer Than What? Older Than What?’, in Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller and Jeffrey Paul, eds, Liberalism: Old and New, 1–15, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Michael (1991) ‘Sovereignty and Exchange in the Orders of Modernity’, Alternatives: Global, Local, Political 16: 447–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Michael (1999) ‘The Ethics of Encounter: Unreading, Unmapping the Imperium’, in David Campbell and Michael Shapiro, eds, Moral Spaces: Rethinking Ethics and World Politics, 57–91, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shilliam, Robbie (2010) ‘Modernity and Modernization’, in Robert Denemark, ed., The International Studies Encyclopedia, 5214–32, Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Jon (1995) Foucault and the Political, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spragens, Thomas A. (2007) ‘Populist Perfectionism: The Other American Liberalism’, in Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller and Jeffrey Paul, eds, Liberalism: Old and New, 141–63, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Robert (2005) ‘Kantian Personal Autonomy’, Political Theory 33 (5): 602–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ten, C.L. (1980) Mill on Liberty, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ten, C.L. (2002) ‘Was Mill a Liberal?’ Politics, Philosophy & Economics 1 (3): 355–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R.B.J. (1988) One World, Many Worlds: Struggles for a Just World Peace, Boulder: Lynne Rienner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R.B.J. (1992) ‘Gender and Critique in the Theory of International Relations’, in V. Spike Peterson, ed., Gendered States: Feminist (Re)Visions of International Relations Theory, 179–202, Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wall, Steven (1998) Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wall, Steven (2001) ‘Neutrality and Responsibility’, The Journal of Philosophy 98: 389–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wall, Steven (2003) ‘Freedom as a Political Ideal’, Social Philosophy and Policy 20 (2): 307–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Cynthia (2010) ‘After Liberalism’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 38 (3): 553–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would especially like to thank Jens Bartelson for his thorough review and helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article, and acknowledge the supportive and critical suggestions from Iver Neumann. A huge debt of gratitude goes to Beate Jahn for her encouragement and friendship, but especially for the chance to work with her as a co-sponsor of the ISA Workshop that has culminated in this special issue. Thank you to Patrick T. Jackson for all of his help and detailed reviews of this article, and finally to the anonymous reviewers whose probing and challenging questions and insights were invaluable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Shinko, R. Geniuses, exiles and (liberal) postmodern subjectivities. J Int Relat Dev 15, 177–200 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2011.32

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2011.32

Keywords

Navigation