Abstract
This article has a threefold aim. First, it criticises the instrumentalisation of intellectual history in international relations (IR) that clouds issues of contemporary politics rather than illuminating them. Second, benefiting from the recent advances in Hobbes’ studies in the field of political theory and emphasising the importance of both textual plausibility and authorial intentions for preserving the ‘horizon’ of the possible interpretations, it suggests that ‘IR’ were of no particular concern to Hobbes, and the few scattered remarks on the ‘superpolitical’ state of the many governments interacting with each other are functionally subservient to the purpose of demonstrating the reality of the state of nature. Third, by pointing to the ‘security continuum’ of various states present in his political theory, the article challenges the reading of Hobbes as authoring the discipline’s foundational inside/outside difference. It concludes by making a case that the field would benefit from curing itself from the ‘Hobsession’ it seems to be suffering and from forgetting Hobbes to open space for rethinking international politics.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
Hobbes, who apparently seems to have been a rather merry, if somewhat anxious, fellow, was epitomised by his enemies as the ‘Devil’s Secretary’, the ‘Monster of Malmesbury’ or the ‘Agent of Hell’ (Parkin, 2007a).
I owe this pun to a colleague Vit Benes at the Institute of International Relations Prague who generously provided comments on an early version of the argument presented here.
The political writings analysed include in particular Leviathan, Behemoth, On the Citizen [De Cive], Human Nature and De Corpore Politico (Elements of Law), A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student, of the Common Laws of England, and the introduction and the translator’s notes to Thucydides’ Eight Books of the Peloponnesian War.
The argument here therefore follows the practice of inquiring into artificially constructed traditions in the discipline and their practical consequences and, more particularly, inquiries into the concept of international anarchy and the conditions under which the realist reading of Hobbes has become dominant in the discipline (see, for example, Ashley, 1988; Walker, 1993; Bell, 2002; Malcolm, 2002; Williams, 2005; Sorrell, 2006; Prokovnik and Slomp, 2011). The volume edited by Prokovnik and Slomp (2011) in particular usefully undermines the distinction in Hobbes’ writings between domestic and international politics. However it also strives, on this basis, to make Hobbes relevant in the current post-sovereign world, thus producing an entire series of ‘Hobbeses’ the modern day international theorists.
Herz (1959) would later credit Butterfield for illuminating the logic of ‘security dilemma’ for the first time, referencing this passage.
A rare instance of classification of Hobbes as a ‘second image’ theorist, the domestic constraints thesis is not convincing because Hobbes seems adamant in claiming that the sovereign is the only judge of war’s necessity, and the counsel he takes only assists him in determining whether the war has a chance of success (A Dialogue, pp. 20–22).
Equality in IR is actually nowhere discussed by Hobbes. The second disanalogy most likely originates from a careless reading of Bull (1977), who summons this argument, originally made by Spinoza in Tractatus Theologico-Politicus 3.11, to prove that Hobbes was an international society theorist. Sleep actually plays a rather positive role for Hobbes, for it gives man, troubled by fear of death and other calamities that may befall him, a rare chance to repose and ‘pause his anxiety’ (Leviathan 12.5). There is little support for the third disanalogy as well, particularly given that the commonwealth is metaphorised as a mortal God and its death is repeatedly identified with civil war (see below).
For another reading of Hobbes that stresses the importance of discipline, see also Devetak (2008, pp. 270–272).
‘Men are therefore in the state of war so long as they judge good and evil by the different measures which their changing desires from time to time dictate’ (De Cive 3.31; cf. Leviathan 15.40).
Earlier suggestions of this linkage are found in Elements of Law 20.5 and De Cive 7.18.
Neither the translation nor the occasional marginal remarks tell much about Hobbes’ view of ‘IR’. Hobbes’s empirical observation in the introductory essay that ‘without pretext, no Warre followes’ and his stressing in a marginal note Thucydides’s conclusion that ‘the truest Quarrell, though least in speech, I conceive to be the growth of the Athenian power’, which incited fear in Lacedaemonians, barely serve as evidence to the contrary (Eight Books, 14; Haslam, 2002, p. 56).
In the Latin Leviathan, Hobbes further gives the example of Cain’s murder of Abel and, in correspondence to François Peleau, also that of soldiers serving in different places and masons who work under different architects. At the same time, he makes it clear that he does not argue that the state of nature once existed all over the world (Skinner, 2008).
This was meant, specifically, to counter the ideological offensive by the Catholic Church, a ‘rogue’ non-state actor of the time according to Hobbes, which used the same media to perpetuate both civil and foreign war (Behemoth, pp. 39–40).
In contrast to the state of nature as a prepolitical condition, where the conflict is overdetermined, brought about by structural causes, epistemic causes and causes pertaining to human nature, regarding the superpolitical condition the only cause implied is structural (absence of common power). Indeed, in A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student Hobbes suggests that under the conditions of anarchy it may be predicted that ‘mutual fear may keep [states] quiet for a time, but upon every visible advantage they will invade one another …’ (A Dialogue, p. 12). This ‘offensive realist’ position, however, should be contextualised. An isolated remark, it is not congruent with Hobbes’ other empirical statements about the superpolitical condition, and it is made in a discussion of the importance of obedience and not by the character in the dialogue with whom Hobbes usually identifies.
Suffice it to say that this set featured both marginalisation and exclusion, and engagement and influence (see Parkin, 2007a, 2007b; Mintz, 1969; Armitage, 2006; Rogers, 2007).
References
Agamben, G. (1998) Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Armitage, D. (2006) Hobbes and the foundations of modern international thought. In: A. Brett, J. Tully and H. Hamilton-Bleakley (eds.) Rethinking the Foundations of Modern International Thought. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Ashley, R. (1988) Untying the sovereign states: A double reading of the anarchy problematique. Millenium 17 (2): 227–262.
Baumgold, D. (2008) The difficulties of Hobbes interpretation. Political Theory 36 (6): 827–855.
Baylis, J. and Smith, S. (2005) The Globalization of World Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bell, D. (2002) Anarchy, power and death: Contemporary political realism as ideology. Journal of Political Ideologies 7 (2): 221–239.
Brett, A. (2003) Liberty, Right and Nature. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Brown, C. (2005) Understanding International Relations. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Bull, H. (1977) Anarchical Society. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Bull, H. (1981) Hobbes and the international anarchy. Social Research 48 (4): 717–738.
Butterfield, H. (1949) Christianity and History. London: G. Bell and Sons.
Campbell, D. (1998) Writing Security. Minneapolis, MN: Minneapolis University Press.
Chandler, D. (2006) Empire in Denial. London: Pluto Press.
Devetak, R. (2008) Foucault, discipline and Raison d’État in early modern Europe. International Political Sociology 2 (3): 270–272.
Eggers, D. (2005) Hobbes’ theory of the state of nature (1640–1668). MPhil thesis, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, UK.
Foucault, M. (2003) Society Must Be Defended. New York: Picador.
Gadamer, H.-G. (2004) Truth and Method. London: Continuum.
Gilpin, R. (1984) The richness of the tradition of political realism. International Organization 38 (2): 287–304.
Haslam, J. (2002) No Virtue Without Necessity. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Herz, J. (1959) International Politics in the Atomic Age. New York: Columbia University Press.
Hobbes, T. (1634) Introduction and translator’s notes. In: Thucydides Eight Books of the Peloponnesian War. London: Richard Mynne.
Hobbes, T. (1969) Behemoth. London: Frank Cass.
Hobbes, T. (1995) Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hobbes, T. (1998) On the Citizen [De Cive]. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hobbes, T. (1999) Human Nature and De Corpore Politico (Elements of Law). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hobbes, T. (2005) A Dialogue Between a Philosopher and a Student, of the Common Laws of England. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hoekstra, K. (1997) Hobbes and the Foole. Political Theory 25 (5): 620–654.
Hoekstra, K. (1998) The savage, the citizen and the foole: The compulsion of civil society in the philosophy of Thomas Hobbes. DPhil thesis, University of Oxford, Oxford.
Hoekstra, K. (2007) Hobbes on the natural condition of mankind. In: P. Springborg (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes’s Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hoffmann, S. (1965) The State of War. London: Pall Mall Press.
Hoffmann, S. (1981) Duties Beyond Borders. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.
Jackson, R. and Sørensen, G. (1999) Introduction to International Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Keohane, R. (1984) After Hegemony. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Kratochwil, F. (1989) Rules, Norms and Decisions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Malcolm, N. (2002) Aspects of Hobbes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Malcolm, N. (2007a) Reason of State, Propaganda and the Thirty Years’ War. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Malcolm, N. (2007b) The name and nature of leviathan. Intellectual History Review 17 (1): 29–57.
Mearsheimer, J. (2001) The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York: W.W. Norton.
Meinecke, F. (1957) Machiavellism. London: Routledge.
Mintz, S. (1969) The Hunting of Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Morgenthau, H. (1965) Politics Among Nations. New York: Knopf.
Parkin, J. (2007a) Taming the Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Parkin, J. (2007b) Reception of Hobbes’s leviathan. In: P. Springborg (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes’s Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 441–459.
Plato (1988) The Laws of Plato. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Prokovnik, R. and Slomp, G. (eds.) (2011) International Political Theory after Hobbes. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
Prozorov, S. (2011) The state of nature as a site of happy life: On Giorgio Agamben’s reading of Hobbes. In: R. Prokovnik and G. Slomp (eds.) International Political Theory After Hobbes. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
Rogers, G.A.J. (2007) Hobbes and his contemporaries. In: P. Springborg (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes’s Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 413–440.
Schmitt, C. (1996) The Concept of the Political. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Skinner, Q. (1966) The ideological context of Hobbes’s political thought. Historical Journal 9 (3): 286–317.
Skinner, Q. (1997) Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Q. (2002a) Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas. In: Visions of Politics I. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 57–89.
Skinner, Q. (2002b) Conquest and consent: Hobbes and the engagement controversy. In: Visions of Politics III. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 287–307.
Skinner, Q. (2008) Hobbes and Republican Liberty. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Sorrell, T. (2006) Hobbes on trade, consumption and international order. The Monist 89 (2): 245–258.
Strauss, L. (1952) The Political Philosophy of Hobbes. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Thucydides (1634) Eight Books of the Peloponnesian War. London: Richard Mynne.
Tralau, J. (2007) Leviathan: The beast of myth. In: P. Springborg (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes’s Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Tricaud, F. (1988) Hobbes’ conception of the state of nature. In: G.A.J. Rogers and A. Ryan (eds.) Perspectives on Thomas Hobbes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tuck, R. (1993) Philosophy and Government. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Tuck, R. (2001) The Rights of War and Peace. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tuck, R. (2004) The Utopianism of Leviathan. In: T. Sorell and L. Foisneau (eds.) Hobbes after 350 Years. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Vincent, J. (1981) The Hobbesian tradition in the twentieth century international thought. Millenium 10 (2): 91–101.
Walker, R.B.J. (1993) Inside-Outside. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, M.C. (1996) Hobbes and international relations: A reconsideration. International Organization 50 (2): 213–236.
Williams, M.C. (2005) The Realist Tradition and the Limits of International Relations. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, M.C. (2006) The Hobbesian theory of international relations. In: B. Jahn (ed.) Classical Theory of International Relations. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Walker, R.B.J. (2011) Hobbes, origins, limits. In: R. Prokovnik and G. Slomp (eds.) International Political Theory after Hobbes. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 168–188.
Waltz, K. (1959) Man, the State and War. New York: Columbia University Press.
Waltz, K. (2008) Realism and International Politics. London: Routledge.
Warrender, H. (1961) The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: His Theory of Obligation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Wendt, A. (1999) Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Wight, M. (1966) Why is there no international theory. In: Diplomatic Investigations. London: Allen and Unwin.
Wight, M. (1991) International Theory: The Three Traditions. Leicester, UK: Leicester University Press.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Ditrych, O. Forget Hobbes. Int Polit 53, 285–302 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1057/ip.2016.6
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/ip.2016.6
Keywords
- Hobbes
- state of nature
- inside/outside
- security continuum
- Skinner
- Foucault