The existing approach to skewness preference
The theoretical justification for considering skewness preference has so far been a Taylor series approximation of the EU. Specifically, letting F be the distribution function for random variable x̃,
Clearly if we have a cubic utility function u(x)=c0+c1x+c2x2+c3x3, the cubic expansion will be precise and the EU given F can be explicitly calculated as
That is, if either the Taylor series represents a good approximation or the utility is cubic, u′′′(x)>0 appears to imply a preference for the unstandardized third central moment m̂
F
3.Footnote 14 On the one hand, our results in the previous section can be seen as confirming that the EU given a distribution can be written as a function of its mean, variance, and unstandardized third moment for mutually skewness-comparable distributions: since we have shown that a function U(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3)=∫
a
bu(x)dF(x) is well defined for skewness-comparable changes in F, for such changes we can define
On the other hand, what (3), (4), and (5) all say is that, assuming u′′′(x)>0, a larger m̂
F
3 implies a larger Eu(x̃) if μ
F
and σ
F
2 are held constant. For two distributions F and G with σ
F
2>σ
G
2, in particular, m̂
F
3>m̂
G
3 does not imply either that F is more skewed than G or that skewness plays any role in determining their comparative desirability to an individual. This seems to be an insight well-hidden in using the traditional approach, as is exemplified by Tsiang's (1972, p. 363) attempt to explain the Borch (1969) paradox by invoking skewness preference.Footnote 15 Other pitfalls in using the traditional approach can also be seen in Markowitz's (1952a) conjecture on skewness preference and the decision to gamble discussed in what follows.
Skewness preference and the decision to gamble
Skewness preference has been associated with gambling since long before the work of Golec and Tamarkin (1998) and Garrett and Sobel (1999). Markowitz (1952a) suggests that “the third moment of the probability distribution of returns from the portfolio may be connected with a propensity to gamble” and that if individuals’ utility of a probability distribution is a function of the third moment as well as the mean and variance of the distribution, then some fair bets would be accepted.Footnote 16 So is it possible for an individual with a third-moment utility function who is averse to larger variances, as is usually assumed in the context of mean-variance analysis, to accept an independent fair gamble given a sufficiently strong skewness preference? The Taylor approximation in (3) gives the impression that this is possible. To examine the possibility, suppose an individual with initial wealth distribution F is contemplating taking fair gambles that increase the skewness of F in the sense defined in this paper and are independent of F. Then
is well defined. Consider first the case where U(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3) is decreasing in σ
F
2 and increasing in m
F
3 for all distribution F. Theorem 2a clearly indicates that U(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3) being decreasing in σ
F
2 for all distribution F is equivalent to risk aversion (i.e., u′′(x)<0 for all x) and since accepting a fair gamble independent of his initial wealth induces a MPS, by the classic result of Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970), it always reduces his EU given his risk aversion whatever the strength of his skewness preference. Alternatively, assume that for all distribution F, Û(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m̂
F
3) is decreasing in σ
F
2 and increasing in m
F
3, that is, (assuming differentiability) Û2(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m̂
F
3)<0 and Û3(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m̂
F
3)>0. Then since U(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3)=Û(μ
F
,σ
F
2,σ
F
3m
F
3), simple differentiation shows that
Clearly, Û2(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3)<0 for all distribution F implies U2(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3)<0 for all distribution F because if U2(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3)⩾0 for a negatively skewed or symmetrical distribution F, that is, m
F
3⩽0, then (given 3(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m̂
F
3)>0) Û2(μ
F
,σ
F
2,m
F
3)⩾0. In other words, with a third-moment utility function, whether the utility is defined on the standardized or unstandardized third moment, aversion to larger variances implies risk aversion and precludes taking fair gambles whatever the strength of the skewness preference.
The incentive effects of tax reforms
In considering the implications of his pioneering analysis of skewness preference, Tsiang (1972, p. 370) suggests that
the effect of income tax on risk-taking should be examined not only with respect to its impacts on the mean and variance of investment returns after tax, but also with respect to its impacts on the skewness of net returns. A progressive income tax ... could certainly have a greater adverse effect on the willingness to take risk than a proportional tax with perfect loss offset that leave the mean and variance after tax at the same levels.
Does a progressive tax necessarily reduce the skewness of the net returns of a risky investment and hence have a greater adverse effect on the willingness to take risk than a proportional income tax? More generally, since the 1980s, there has been a broad international trend towards the flattening of personal income tax structures. Does such a reform increase the skewness of the after-tax income distribution and as a result, other things being equal, enhance the incentive to make risky investments? Our basic results on skewness preference can be applied to give definitive answers to these questions, under a particular definition of a “more progressive tax” as follows.Footnote 17
Definition 6
That is, a tax schedule t1(x) is more progressive than another t2(x) in the sense of residual concavity if the residual income function [x−t1(x)] is a concave transformation of [x−t2(x)]. Under this definition, any graduated-rate tax is more residual-concave than any proportional tax and a tax schedule becoming less residual-concave more generally defines a particular kind of flattening of the tax schedule. For example, flattening a graduated-rate tax by reducing the top marginal tax rate or by abolishing the income band where the highest marginal tax rate applies leads to a less residual concave tax schedule.Footnote 18 We next show that in most relevant cases in practice, a more residual-concave tax schedule is a more progressive one as is usually defined in the literature on income inequality measurement (see, e.g., Lambert (2001)).
Proposition 2
-
Suppose r1(r2−1(0))⩾0. Then a tax schedule t1(x) has more residual progression than t2(x), that is, [x−t1(x)]/[x−t2(x)] is non-increasing for all x, if t1(x) is more residual-concave than t2(x).
The condition r1(r2−1(0))⩾0, which is equivalent to [x−t2(x)]=0 implying [x−t1(x)]⩾0, is clearly satisfied if we only consider tax schedules involving no lump-sum elements, that is, t
i
(0)=0, in which case r1(r2−1(0))=0. Typical real-world tax schedules with a personal allowance, that is, an amount subtracted from pre-tax income in arriving at taxable income, are clearly in this category.
Given Definition 6, Lemmas 2 and 3 immediately imply the following.
Proposition 3
-
For a given pre-tax income distribution, let F and G denote the after-tax income distributions under tax schedules t1(x) and t2(x), respectively. If t1(x) is more residual-concave than t2(x), then G is more skewed to the right than F and m
G
>m
F
.
For an interpretation of the result, suppose an investor's initial income is non-random and F and G represent the after-tax prospective income distributions given a risky investment under tax schedules t1(x) and t2(x), respectively. The result implies that if t1(x) is more residual-concave than t2(x), we can decompose the effect on the EU of the change of tax schedules from t1 to t2 as in (1)
where F1(x)≡F(x+μ
F
−μ
G
) and
. That is, not only does a tax flattening in the form of the change from t1 to t2 unequivocablly increase the skewness of the prospective income distribution but how it affects the attractiveness of the investment is completely determined by its effect on the mean, variance, and third moment of the after-tax distribution. Furthermore, assuming skewness preference, such a tax reform increases the attractiveness of the investment compared with a “skewness-neutral” tax reform that achieves the same effects on the mean and the variance of the after-tax income distribution. More specifically, noting the relationship between F2(x) and F(x), if a tax schedule t3(x) is such that
, then t3(x) clearly induces an after-tax income distribution equal to F2(x) (which has the same mean and variance as G(x)) and a tax reform from t1(x) to t2(x) clearly makes the investment more attractive compared with the reform from t1(x) to t3(x). Since any graduated-rate (i.e., convex) tax schedule is more residual-concave than a proportional tax as remarked earlier, a corollary of this is a formal validation of Tsiang's conjecture if a progressive tax is understood to be a graduated-rate tax: Any graduated-rate tax has a greater adverse effect on the attractiveness of a risky investment than a proportional tax with perfect loss offset that leaves the mean and variance after tax at the same levels.Footnote 19