Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 1, Issue 2, pp 97–125 | Cite as

Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality

  • Andreas Weber
  • Francisco J. Varela
Article

Abstract

This paper proposes a basic revision of the understanding of teleology in biological sciences. Since Kant, it has become customary to view purposiveness in organisms as a bias added by the observer; the recent notion of teleonomy expresses well this “as-if” character of natural purposes. In recent developments in science, however, notions such as self-organization (or complex systems) and the autopoiesis viewpoint, have displaced emergence and circular self-production as central features of life. Contrary to an often superficial reading, Kant gives a multi-faceted account of the living, and anticipates this modern reading of the organism, even introducing the term “self-organization” for the first time. Our re-reading of Kant in this light is strengthened by a group of philosophers of biology, with Hans Jonas as the central figure, who put back on center stage an organism-centered view of the living, an autonomous center of concern capable of providing an interior perspective. Thus, what is present in nuce in Kant, finds a convergent development from this current of philosophy of biology and the scientific ideas around autopoeisis, two independent but parallel developments culminating in the 1970s. Instead of viewing meaning or value as artifacts or illusions, both agree on a new understanding of a form of immanent teleology as truly biological features, inevitably intertwined with the self-establishment of an identity which is the living process.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

A. General

  1. Allen, C., Bekoff, M., and Lauder, G. 1998. Nature's Purposes: Analyses of Function and Design in Biology. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  2. Barbaras, R. 1999. Le désir et la distance. Paris: J. Vrin.Google Scholar
  3. Bedau, M. 1992. Where's the good in teleology? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52: 781-805.Google Scholar
  4. Bedau, M. 1996. The nature of life. In: M.A. Boden (ed), The Philosophy of Artificial Life, pp. 332-357. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Boaden, M. A. 1996. Autonomy and artificiality. In: M. A. Boaden (ed), The Philosophy of Artificial Life, pp. 95-108. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Böhme, G. and Böhme, H. 1983. Das Andere der Vernunft: Zur Entwicklung von Rationalitätsstrukturen am Beispiel Kant. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  7. Cornell, J. F. 1986. A Newton of the Grassblade? Darwin and the problem of organic teleology. Isis 77: 405-421.Google Scholar
  8. Dawkins, R. 1987. The Blind Watchmaker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Grünewald, B. 1996. Teleonomie und reflektierende Urteilskraft. In: A. Riebel and R. Hiltscher (eds), Wahrheit und Geltung: Festschrift für Werner Flach, pp. 63-84. Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann.Google Scholar
  10. Hösle, V. 1994. Ontologie und Ethik bei Hans Jonas. In: D. Böhler (ed), Ethik für die Zukunft. Im Diskurs mit Hans Jonas. München: C.H. Beck.Google Scholar
  11. Lennox, J. 1993. Darwin was a teleologist. Biology and Philosophy 8: 409-421.Google Scholar
  12. Lenoir, T. 1982. The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanics in 19th Century German Biology. Studies in the History of Modern Science, 13. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  13. Lewontin, R. 1983. The organism as the subject and object of evolution. Scientia 118: 63-82.Google Scholar
  14. McFarland, J. D. 1970. Kant's Concept of Teleology. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh Press.Google Scholar
  15. Mathews, G. B. 1992. De anima 2. 2-4 and the meaning of life. In: M. C. Nussbaum and A. O. Rorty (eds), Essays on Aristotle's De anima, pp. 185-193. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  16. Mayr, E. 1988. Toward a New Philosophy of Biology. London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1994. La Nature. Gallimard, Paris.Google Scholar
  18. Nagel, E. 1977. Teleology revisited. Journal of Philosophy 76: 261-301.Google Scholar
  19. Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A. (eds). 1993. The Quality of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Pittendrigh, C. S. 1958. Adaption, natural selection and behaviour. In: A. Roe and G. G. Simpson (eds), Behaviour and Evolution, pp. 390-419. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Rickert, H. 1911. Philosophie des Lebens. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
  22. Rosenberg, M. L. 1996. Species Diversity in Space and Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Salthe, S. N. 1993. Development and Evolution: Complexity and Change in Biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  24. Strohmann, R. C. 1997. The coming Kuhnian revolution in biology. Nature Biotechnology 15: 194-199.Google Scholar
  25. Thompson, D. 1966. On Growth and Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Varela, F. and Depraz, N. (1999). At the source of time: valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. In: S. Gallagher and S. Watson (eds), Ipseity and Alterity: Interdisciplinary Approaches to Intersubjectivity. Rouen: Presses Universitaires de Rouen.Google Scholar
  27. Weber, B. H. and Depew, D. J. 1996. Natural selection and self organization. Dynamical models as clues to a new evolutionary synthesis. Philosophy and Biology 11: 33-65.Google Scholar
  28. Zumbach, C. 1984. The Transcendent Science. Kant's Conception of Biological Methodology. The Hague: Nijhoff.Google Scholar

B. For the renewed discussion on teleology in the philosophy of biology

  1. Apel, K.-O. 1963. Das Leibapriori der Erkenntnis. Archiv für Philosophie 12: 152-172.Google Scholar
  2. Destrée, P. and Dewitte, J. (eds). 1996. Phénoménologie et philosophie de la nature. Études Phénoménologiques 12: 23-24.Google Scholar
  3. Goodwin, B. C. and Saunders, P. T. (eds). 1989. Theoretical Biology: Epigenetic and Evolutionary Order from Complex Systems. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Gould, S. J. 1991. Wonderful Life. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
  5. Harrington, A. 1996. Reenchanted Science. Holism in German Culture from Wilhelm II to Hitler. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Hoffmeyer, J. 1996. Signs of Meaning in the Universe. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Jantsch, E. 1980. The Self-Organizing Universe. Oxford: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
  8. Jonas, H. 1966. The Phenomenon of Life. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
  9. Jonas, H. 1973: Organismus und Freiheit. Ansätze zu einer philosophischen Biologie. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht. New edition (1994): Das Prinzip Leben. Frankfurt am Main und Leipzig: Insel.Google Scholar
  10. Jonas, H. 1992. Philosophische Untersuchungen und metaphysische Vermutungen, Frankfurt am Main und Leipzig: Insel.Google Scholar
  11. Kauffman, S. A. 1993. Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Kull, K. 1999. Biosemiotics in the twentieth century: a view from biology. Semiotica 127: 385-414.Google Scholar
  13. Löw, R. 1980. Philosophie des Lebendigen. Der Begriff des Organischen bei Kant, sein Grund und seine Aktualität. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  14. Plessner, H. 1975. Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch. Einleitung in die Philosophische Anthropologie. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  15. Plessner, H. 1982. Ein Newton des Grashalms? In: Gesammelte Werke. Bd. 8, pp. 247-266. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  16. Portmann, A. 1948. Die Tiergestalt. Zürich: Rhein-Verlag.Google Scholar
  17. Portmann, A. 1960. Neue Wege der Biologie. München: Piper.Google Scholar
  18. Spaemann, R. and Löw, R. 1981. Die Frage Wozu. Geschichte und Wiederentdeckung des Teleologischen Denkens. München: Piper.Google Scholar
  19. Stein, W. D. and Varela, F. J. (eds). 1991. Thinking about Biology. Santa Fe Studies in the Sciences of Complexity. Addison Wesley.Google Scholar
  20. Uexküll, J. v. 1973. Theoretische Biologie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  21. Uexküll, J. v. 1980. Kompositioslehre der Natur. Biologie als undogmatische Naturwissenschaft. Ausgewählte Schriften. Berlin und Wien: Ullstein.Google Scholar
  22. Uexküll, J. v. and Kriszat, G. 1970. Streifzüge durch die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen. Bedeutungslehre. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer. (English translation in Semiotica 90: 319-391. Special Issue with an introduction by Th. v. Uexküll).Google Scholar
  23. Weber, A. (2001). Turning the inside out: natural forms as expression of intentionality. Sign Systems Studies 29 (1): 153-168.Google Scholar
  24. Webster, G. and Goodwin, B. C. 1982. The origin of species: a structuralist approach. Journal of Social and Biological Structure 5: 15-47.Google Scholar

C. For the introduction and development of autopoiesis and biological autonomy

  1. Deamer, D. W. and Fleischaker, G. R. (eds). 1994. Origins of Life: The Central Concepts. Boston: Jones and Bartlett.Google Scholar
  2. Fleischaker, G. R. 1990. Origins of life: an operational definition. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere 20: 127-137.Google Scholar
  3. Lazcano, A. 1995. Aleksandr I. Oparin: Apuntes para una Biografía Intelectual. In: F. Móran, J. Peretó, and A. Moreno (eds), Origines de la Vida. Madrid: Editorial Complutense.Google Scholar
  4. Margulis, L. and Sagan, D. 1995. What is Life. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
  5. Maturana, H. and Varela, F. 1980. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Boston: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  6. Maturana, H. and F. Varela. 1987. The Tree of Knowledge: A New Look at the Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Boston: Shambhala/New Science Library.Google Scholar
  7. Mingers, J. 1995. Self-producing Systems: Implications and Applications of Autopoiesis. New York: Plenum Press.Google Scholar
  8. Morowitz, H. J. 1992. Beginnings of Cellular Life. Metabolism Recapitulates Biogenesis. New Haven: Yale University.Google Scholar
  9. Oparin, A. 1938. The Origin of Life on Earth. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  10. Rose, S. P. R. 1998. Lifelines. Biology beyond Determinism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Varela, F. J. 1979. Principles of Biological Autonomy. New York: Elsevier/North-Holland.Google Scholar
  12. Varela, F. J. 1991. Organism: a meshwork of selfless selves. In: A. I. Tauber (ed), Organism and the Origins of Self. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  13. Varela, F. J. 1994. On defining life. In: G. Fleischeker and M. Colonna (eds), Self-reproduction of Supramolecular Structures, pp. 23-33. Nato ASI Series, Plenum Press.Google Scholar
  14. Varela, F. J. 1996. The early days of autopoiesis: Heinz von Foerster and Chile. Systems Research 13: 407-417.Google Scholar
  15. Varela, F. J. 1997. Patterns of life: intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition 34: 72-84.Google Scholar
  16. Varela, F., Maturana, H., and Uribe, R. 1974. Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. Biosystems 5: 187-196.Google Scholar
  17. Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. 1991. The Embodied Mind. Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2002

Authors and Affiliations

  • Andreas Weber
    • 1
  • Francisco J. Varela
  1. 1.Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin, Kulturwissenschaftliches SeminarBerlinGermany

Personalised recommendations