Philosophical Studies

, Volume 118, Issue 3, pp 339–371 | Cite as

Spatio-Temporal Coincidence and the Grounding Problem

  • Karen Bennett

Abstract

A lot of people believe that distinct objectscan occupy precisely the same place for theentire time during which they exist. Suchpeople have to provide an answer to the`grounding problem' – they have to explain howsuch things, alike in so many ways, nonethelessmanage to fall under different sortals, or havedifferent modal properties. I argue in detailthat they cannot say that there is anything invirtue of which spatio-temporally coincidentthings have those properties. However, I alsoargue that this may not be as bad as it looks,and that there is a way to make sense of theclaim that such properties are primitive.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Baker, L. (1997): ‘Why Constitution is not Identity’, The Journal of Philosophy 94, 599–621.Google Scholar
  2. Baker, L. (2000): Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bennett, K. (forthcoming): ‘Global Supervenience and Dependence’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
  4. Black, M. (1954): ‘The Identity of Indiscernibles’, reprinted (1970) in M. Loux (ed.), Universals and Particulars: Readings in Ontology (pp. 204–216), Garden City, NY: Doubleday.Google Scholar
  5. Blackburn, S. (1973): ‘Moral Realism’, reprinted (1993) in Essays in Quasi-Realism (pp. 111–129), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Blackburn, S. (1984): Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Blackburn, S. (1985): ‘Supervenience Revisited’, reprinted (1993) in Essays in Quasi-Realism (pp. 130–148), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Blackburn, S. (1987): ‘Morals and Modals’, reprinted (1993) in Essays in Quasi-Realism (pp. 52–74), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Burke, M. (1992): ‘Copper Statues and Pieces of Copper: A Challenge to the Standard Account’, Analysis 52, 12–17.Google Scholar
  10. Burke, M. (1994): ‘Preserving the Principle of One Object to a Place: A Novel Account of the Relations Among Objects, Sorts, Sortals, and Persistence Conditions’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54, 591–624.Google Scholar
  11. Della Rocca, M. (1996): ‘Essentialists and Essentialism’, The Journal of Philosophy 93, 186–202.Google Scholar
  12. Divers, J. (1992): ‘Modal Supervenience and Modal Realism’, Theoria 58, 99–115.Google Scholar
  13. Fine, K. (2003): ‘The Non-Identity of aMaterial Thing and its Matter’, Mind 112, 195–234.Google Scholar
  14. Forbes, G. (1985): The Metaphysics of Modality, Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  15. Geach, P. (1980): Reference and Generality, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Gibbard, A. (1975): ‘Contingent Identity’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 4, 187–221.Google Scholar
  17. Hare, R.M. (1952): The Language of Morals, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  18. Heller, M. (1990): The Ontology of Physical Objects: Four-Dimensional Hunks of Matter, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Horgan, T. (1993): ‘From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World’, Mind 102, 555–586.Google Scholar
  20. Kim, J. (1984): ‘Concepts of Supervenience’, reprinted (1993) in Supervenience and Mind (pp. 53–78), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Kim, J. (1988): ‘Supervenience for Multiple Domains’, reprinted (1993) in Supervenience and Mind (pp. 109–130), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Kim, J. (1993): ‘Postscripts on Supervenience’, in Supervenience and Mind (pp. 161–171), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Kim, J. (1998): Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental Causation, Cambridge,MA: Bradford.Google Scholar
  24. Kripke, S. (1980): Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Lewis, D. (1971): ‘Counterparts of Persons and Their Bodies’, reprinted (1983) in Philosophical Papers, Volume I (pp. 47–54), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Lewis, D. (1986): On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  27. Lewis, D. (1993): ‘Many but Almost One’, reprinted (1999) in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology (pp. 64–182), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  28. McGinn, C. (1981): ‘Modal Reality’, in R. Healey (ed.), Reduction, Time, and Reality: Studies in the Philosophy of the Natural Sciences (pp. 143–188), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  29. McLaughlin, B. (1995): ‘Varieties of Supervenience’, in E. Savellos and U. Yalçin (eds.), Supervenience: New Essays (pp.16–59), NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  30. McLaughlin, B. (1997): ‘Supervenience, Vagueness, and Determination’, Philosophical Perspectives 11, 209–230.Google Scholar
  31. Moyer, M. (unpublished): ‘Defending Coincidence: An Explanation of a Sort'.Google Scholar
  32. Myro, G. (1986a): ‘Identity and Time’, in E. Grandy and R. Warner (eds.), Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends (pp. 383–409), Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  33. Myro, G. (1986b): ‘Time and Essence’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 11, 331–341.Google Scholar
  34. Noonan, H. (1980): Objects and Identity, The Hague: Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  35. Noonan, H. (1993): ‘Constitution is Identity’, Mind 102, 133–146.Google Scholar
  36. Paul, L.A. (forthcoming): ‘The Context of Essence’, The Australasian Journal of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  37. Quine, W.V.O. (1960): Word and Object, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  38. Rea, M. (1997): ‘Supervenience and Colocation’, American PhilosophicalQuarterly 34, 367–375.Google Scholar
  39. Rea, M. (2000): ‘Constitution and Kind Membership’, Philosophical Studies 97, 169–193.Google Scholar
  40. Sidelle, A. (1989): Necessity, Essence, and Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Sidelle, A. (1992a): ‘Identity and the Identity-Like’, Philosophical Topics 20, 269–292.Google Scholar
  42. Sidelle, A. (1992b): ‘Rigidity, Ontology, and Semantic Structure’, The Journal of Philosophy 89, 410–430.Google Scholar
  43. Sider, T. (1999): ‘Global Supervenience and Identity Across Times and Worlds’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59, 913–937.Google Scholar
  44. Sider, T. (2001): Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time, Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  45. Sosa, E. (1987): ‘Subjects Among Other Things’, Philosophical Perspectives 1, 155–187.Google Scholar
  46. Sosa, E. (1999): ‘Existential Relativity’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, 132–143.Google Scholar
  47. Stalnaker, R. (1996): ‘Varieties of Supervenience’, Philosophical Perspectives 10, 221–241.Google Scholar
  48. Thomson, J. (1998): ‘The Statue and the Clay’, Noûs 32, 149–173.Google Scholar
  49. Unger, P. (1980): ‘The Problem of the Many’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5, 411–468.Google Scholar
  50. Wiggins, D. (1980): Sameness and Substance, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Wiggins, D. (1986): ‘On Singling Out an Object Determinately’, in P. Pettit and J. McDowell (eds.), Subject, Thought, and Context (pp. 169–180), Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  52. Williamson, T. (1994): Vagueness, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
  53. Yablo, S. (1987): ‘Identity, Essence, and Indiscernibility’, The Journal of Philosophy 84, 293–314.Google Scholar
  54. Yablo, S. (1992): Mental Causation’, The Philosophical Review 101, 245–280.Google Scholar
  55. Zimmerman, D. (1995): ‘Theories of Masses and Problems of Constitution’, The Philosophical Review 104, 53–110.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2004

Authors and Affiliations

  • Karen Bennett
    • 1
  1. 1.Princeton UniversityUSA and Australian National University E-mail

Personalised recommendations