Journal of Philosophical Logic

, Volume 33, Issue 1, pp 27–88 | Cite as

A Contextual-Hierarchical Approach to Truth and the Liar Paradox

  • Michael Glanzberg

Abstract

This paper presents an approach to truth and the Liar paradox which combines elements of context dependence and hierarchy. This approach is developed formally, using the techniques of model theory in admissible sets. Special attention is paid to showing how starting with some ideas about context drawn from linguistics and philosophy of language, we can see the Liar sentence to be context dependent. Once this context dependence is properly understood, it is argued, a hierarchical structure emerges which is neither ad hoc nor unnatural.

admissible sets infinitary logic Liar paradox truth 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Barwise, J.: Admissible Sets and Structures, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1975.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Barwise, J. and Etchemendy, J.: The Liar, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1987.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Burge, T.: Semantical paradox, J. Phil. 76 (1979), 169-198. Reprinted in [37].Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Burgess, J. P.: The truth is never simple, J. Symbolic Logic 51 (1986), 663-681.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Büring, D.: Topic, in P. Bosch and R. van der Sandt (eds), Focus: Linguistic, Cognitive, and Computational Perspectives, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999, pp. 142-165.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Carnap, R.: Meaning and Necessity, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1947.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Cutland, N.: Model theory on admissible sets, Ann. of Math. Logic 5 (1973), 257-289.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Feferman, S.: Some applications of the notions of forcing and generic sets, Fund. Math. 56 (1965), 325-345.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Feferman, S.: Toward useful type-free theories, I, J. Symbolic Logic 49 (1984), 75-111. Reprinted in [37].Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Gaifman, H.: Operational pointer semantics: Solution to self-referential puzzles I, in M. Y. Vardi (ed.), Proceedings of the Second Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge, Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, 1988, pp. 43-59.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Gaifman, H.: Pointers to truth, J. Philos. 89 (1992), 223-261.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Gaifman, H.: Pointers to propositions, in A. Chapuis and A. Gupta (eds), Circularity, Definition and Truth, Indian Council of Philosophical Research, New Delhi, 2000, pp. 79-121.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Gilmore, P. C.: The consistency of partial set theory without extensionality, in T. J. Jech (ed.) Axiomatic Set Theory, Part II of Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., 13, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, 1974, pp. 147-153.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Glanzberg, M.: The Liar in context, Philos. Stud. 103 (2001), 217-251.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Glanzberg, M.: Supervenience and infinitary logic, Nous 35 (2001), 419-439.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Glanzberg, M.: Topic and discourse, Mind and Language 17 (2002), 333-375.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Glanzberg, M.: Truth, reflection, and hierarchies, Synthese, forthcoming.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Grosz, B. J.: The representation and use of focus in a system for understanding dialogs, in Proceedings of the Fifth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, 1977, pp. 67-76. Reprinted in [21].Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Grosz, B. J., Joshi, A. K. and Weinstein, S.: Centering: A framework for modelling the local coherence of discourse, Computational Linguistics 21 (1995), 203-225.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Grosz, B. J. and Sidner, C. L.: Attention, intentions, and the structure of discourse, Computational Linguistics 12 (1986), 175-204.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Grosz, B. J., Sparck Jones, K. and Webber, B. L. (eds): Readings in Natural Language Processing, Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, 1986.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Gupta, A.: Truth and paradox, J. Philos. Logic 11 (1982), 1-60. Reprinted in [37].Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Heim, I.: The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, 1982. Published by Garland, New York, 1989.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Hinman, P. G.: Recursion-Theoretic Hierarchies, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1978.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Jeffrey, R. C.: The Logic of Decision, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1965.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Kamp, H.: A theory of truth and semantic representation, in J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen and M. Stokhof (eds), Truth, Interpretation, and Information, Foris, Dordrecht, 1984, pp. 1-41.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Karttunen, L.: Discourse referents, in J. D. McCawley (ed.), Notes from the Linguistic Underground, Syntax and Semantics 7, Academic Press, New York, 1976, pp. 363-385.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Keisler, H. J.: Model Theory for Infinitary Logic, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1971.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Keisler, H. J.: Forcing and the omitting types theorem, in M. D. Morely (ed.), Studies in Model Theory, Math. Assoc. of America, Buffalo, 1973, pp. 96-133.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Koons, R. C.: Paradoxes of Belief and Strategic Rationality, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1992.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Kratzer, A.: An investigation of the lumps of thought, Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (1989), 607-653.Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Kripke, S.: Outline of a theory of truth, J. Philos. 72 (1975), 690-716. Reprinted in [37].Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Larson, R. K.: Implicit arguments in situation semantics, Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (1988), 169-201.Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Lewis, D.: Scorekeeping in a language game, J. Philos. Logic 8 (1979), 339-359. Reprinted in [35].Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Lewis, D.: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1983.Google Scholar
  36. 36.
    Ludlow, P.: The adicity of ‘believes’ and the hidden indexical theory, Analysis 56 (1996), 97-102.Google Scholar
  37. 37.
    Martin, R. L. (ed.): Recent Essays on Truth and the Liar Paradox, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1984.Google Scholar
  38. 38.
    McGee, V.: Truth, Vagueness, and Paradox, Hackett, Indianapolis, 1991.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    McNally, L.: On recent formal analyses of topic, in J. Ginzburg, Z. Khasidashvili, C. Vogel, J.-J. Lévy and E. Vallduví (eds), The Tbilisi Symposium on Logic, Language and Computation, CSLI, Stanford, 1998, pp. 147-160.Google Scholar
  40. 40.
    Moschovakis, Y. N.: Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1974.Google Scholar
  41. 41.
    Nadel, M.: More Löwenheim-Skolem results for admissible sets, Israel J. Math. 18 (1974), 53-64.Google Scholar
  42. 42.
    Nadel, M.: Scott sentences and admissible sets, Ann. of Math. Logic 7 (1974), 267-294.Google Scholar
  43. 43.
    Parsons, C.: The Liar paradox, J. Philos. Logic 3 (1974), 381-412. Reprinted in [37].Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    Portner, P. and Yabushita, K.: The semantics and pragmatics of topic phrases, Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (1998), 117-157.Google Scholar
  45. 45.
    Reinhart, T.: Pragmatics and linguistics: An analysis of sentence topics, Philosophica 27 (1981), 53-94.Google Scholar
  46. 46.
    Roberts, C.: Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics, Ohio State University Working Papers in Linguistics 49 (1996), 91-136.Google Scholar
  47. 47.
    Sacks, G. E.: Higher Recursion Theory, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1990.Google Scholar
  48. 48.
    Simmons, K.: Universality and the Liar, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993.Google Scholar
  49. 49.
    Simmons, K.: Three paradoxes: Circles and singularities, in A. Chapuis and A. Gupta (eds), Circularity, Definition and Truth, Indian Council of Philosophical Research, New Delhi, 2000, pp. 333-354.Google Scholar
  50. 50.
    Soames, S.: Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content, Philosophical Topics 15 (1987), 47-87.Google Scholar
  51. 51.
    Stalnaker, R. C.: Assertion, in P. Cole (ed.), Pragmatics, Syntax and Semantics 9, Academic Press, New York, 1978, pp. 315-322. Reprinted in [53].Google Scholar
  52. 52.
    Stalnaker, R. C.: Inquiry, MIT Press, Cambridge, 1984.Google Scholar
  53. 53.
    Stalnaker, R. C.: Context and Content, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999.Google Scholar
  54. 54.
    Stanley, J.: Context and logical form, Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (2000), 391-434.Google Scholar
  55. 55.
    Stanley, J. and Gendler Szabó, Z.: On quantifier domain restriction, Mind and Language 15 (2000), 219-261.Google Scholar
  56. 56.
    Tarski, A.: Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalizierten Sprachen, Studia Philosophica 1 (1935), 261-405. References are to the translation by J. H. Woodger as “The concept of truth in formalized languages” [57].Google Scholar
  57. 57.
    Tarski, A.: Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, 2nd edn, Hackett, Indianapolis, 1983. Edited by J. Corcoran with translations by J. H. Woodger.Google Scholar
  58. 58.
    Vallduví, E.: The informational component, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania, 1990. Published by Garland, New York, 1992.Google Scholar
  59. 59.
    van Eijck, J. and Kamp, H.: Representing discourse in context, in J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen (eds), Handbook of Logic and Language, Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1997, pp. 179-237.Google Scholar
  60. 60.
    van Fraassen, B. C.: Presupposition, implication, and self-reference, J. Philos. 65 (1968), 136-152.Google Scholar
  61. 61.
    van Kuppevelt, J.: Discourse structure, topicality and questioning, J. Linguistics 31 (1995), 109-147.Google Scholar
  62. 62.
    von Fintel, K.: Restrictions on quantifier domains, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, 1994.Google Scholar
  63. 63.
    Walker, M.: Centering, anaphora resolution, and discourse structure, in M. Walker, A. Joshi and E. Prince (eds), Centering in Discourse, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1997, pp. 401-435.Google Scholar
  64. 64.
    Ward, G. L.: The semantics and pragmatics of preposing, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania, 1985. Published by Garland, New York, 1988.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2004

Authors and Affiliations

  • Michael Glanzberg

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations