Skip to main content

How long is “now”? Phenomenology and the specious present

Abstract

The duration of “now” is shown to be important not only for an understanding of how conscious beings sense duration, but also for the validity of the phenomenological enterprise as Husserl conceived it. If “now” is too short, experiences can not be described before they become memories, which can be considered to be transcendent rather than immanent phenomena and therefore inadmissible as phenomenological data. Evidence concerning (a) the objective duration of sensations in various sensory modalities, (b) the time necessary for sensations to enter consciousness and (c) the variability in the subjective sense of time's passing under different conditions is used to conclude that the duration of “now” can actually vary under normal conditions from about 10 ms to several seconds and in extreme cases up to several hours. Thus the immanent moment can be long enough to encompass a report of the contents of consciousness, making phenomenology a viable project. A further speculation from the evidence described is that consciousness takes discrete samples of the external world, at a rate inversely proportional to the duration of the “now” moment.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

References

  1. Churchland, P. S. 1981. On the alleged backwards referral of experiences and its relevance to the mind-body problem. Philosophy of Science 48: 165–181.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Fehrer, E. and Biederman, I. A. 1962. A comparison of reaction time and verbal report in the detection of masked stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology 64: 126–130.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Garde, M. M. and Cowey, A. 2000. “Deaf hearing” unacknowledged detection of auditory stimuli in a patient with cerebral deafness. Cortex 36: 71–80.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Glynn, I. M. 1990. Consciousness and time. Nature 348: 477–479.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Gomes, G. 1998. The timing of conscious experience: a critical review and reinterpretation of Libet's research. Consciousness and Cognition 7: 559–595.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Husserl, E. 1991. On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893–1917), trans. J. B. Brough. In: Edmund Husserl Collected Works IV. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  7. James, W. 1890. The Principles of Psychology. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Kandel, E. R., Schwartz, J. H. and Jessell, T. M. 1991. Principles of Neural Science. London and Sidney: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Libet, B. 1993. Neurophysiology of Consciousness: Selected Papers and New Essays by Benjamin Libet. Bosten: Birkhauser.

    Google Scholar 

  10. MacIntyre, N. J. and McComas, A. J. 1996. Non-conscious choice in cutaneous backward masking. Neuroreport 7: 1513–1516.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Penrose, R. 1989. The Emperor's New Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Pockett, S. 1999. Anesthesia and the electrophysiology of auditory consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 8: 45–61.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Pockett, S. 2000. The Nature of Consciousness: A Hypothesis. New York: Iuniverse Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Pockett, S. 2002. On subjective back-referral and how long it takes to become conscious of a stimulus: A reinterpretation of Libet's data. Consciousness and Cognition 11: 144–161.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Weiskrantz, L. 1996. Blindsight revisited. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 6: 215–220.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pockett, S. How long is “now”? Phenomenology and the specious present. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 2, 55–68 (2003). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1022960122740

Download citation

  • specious present
  • time-consciousness
  • objective duration
  • the now
  • consciousness