Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic Foundation for Teaching Critical Thinking in Group Discussion

  • Published:
Interchange Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue for a view of critical thinking and learning as a fallibilistic epistemic process of inquiry and evaluation, which is grounded in human fallibility. I show how this plausible view is different from other views, in that it is predicated not only on individual thinking alone but also on group thinking as it affects the individual in the context of a group discussion. The individualistic rational view of critical thinking only specifies the process or method that one may individually use to evaluate beliefs or the evidence that one brings to bear on one's doxastic attitude or judgment. This view does not specify the nature and scope of evidence that one may need to evaluate. I argue that evaluating a belief in the context of having a substantial amount of available evidence in a social group is important for determining whether one thinks critically. There is epistemic advantage in evaluating a broad scope of available evidence in a group discussion, which does not exist otherwise. I assume that group discussion is a pedagogical tool, which under the right social conditions, is likely to bring about learning and the acquisition of critical thinking abilities. The right social conditions for group discussion can optimize reasonableness by a process which involves cognitive division of labor and epistemic prudence. An individual can evaluate on his or her own only a limited amount of evidence; sometimes we may need to rely on the evidence that others have already evaluated which they may reasonably accept, given their cognitive comparative advantage. I distinguish among three plausible learning outcomes of the process of critical thinking, which indicate cognitive division of labor and comparative epistemic advantage in a group discussion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Annis, D. (1978). A contextual theory of epistemic justification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15, 213–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Annis, D. (1982). A contextual and cultural component of epistemic justification — A reply. Philosophia, 12, 51–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridges, D. (1979). Education, democracy and discussion. Windsor, UK: NFER.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burbules, N. (1991). Rationality and reasonableness: A discussion of Harvey Siegel's Relativism refuted and educating reason. Educational Theory, 41(2), 235–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1987). Knowledge, context, social standards. Synthese, 72, 3–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 40, 363–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (1988). Social epistemology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 20, 121–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig, J. (1985). Epistemic dependence. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 335–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1980). Reasoning and evidence one does not possess. In P. French, T. Uehling, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy (pp. 163–182). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, W.F. (1979). Learning through discussion. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1951). Critique of judgment (J.H. Bernard, Trans.). New York: Harner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1971). A proposed definition of propositional knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 471–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (Ed.). (1987). Naturalizing epistemology. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. & Paxson, T. (1969). Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 225–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • McPeck, J. (1981). Critical thinking and education. New York: St. Martins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, W.R., Jr. (1995). ‘Critical Thinking’ — What does that mean? Journal of College Science Teaching, March/April, 336–340.

  • Paul, R.W. (1982). Teaching critical thinking in the 'strong’ sense: A focus on self-deception, world views, and a dialectical mode of analysis. Informal Logic Newsletter, 4(2), 2–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1974). Knowledge and justification. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1985). Truth and approximation to truth. In D. Miller (Ed.), Popper selections (pp. 181–198). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1988). Educating reason. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1974). How do you know? American Philosophical Quarterly, 11(2), 113–122.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ikuenobe, P. Epistemic Foundation for Teaching Critical Thinking in Group Discussion. Interchange 33, 371–393 (2002). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1021564120979

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1021564120979

Navigation