Skip to main content
Log in

Weyl’s Appropriation of Husserl’s and Poincar“s Thought

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article locates Weyl’s philosophy of mathematics and its relationship to his philosophy of science within the epistemological and ontological framework of Husserl’s phenomenology as expressed in the Logical Investigations and Ideas. This interpretation permits a unified reading of Weyl’s scattered philosophical comments in The Continuum and Space-Time-Matter. But the article also indicates that Weyl employed Poincar“s predicativist concerns to modify Husserl’s semantics and trim Husserl’s ontology. Using Poincar“s razor to shave Husserl’s beard leads to limitations on the least upper bound theorem in the foundations of analysis and Dirichlet’s principle in the foundations of physics. Finally, the article opens the possibility of reading Weyl as a systematic thinker, that he follows Husserl’s so-called transcendental turn in the Ideas. This permits an even more unified reading of Weyl’s scattered philosophical comments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Bar-Hillel, Y.: 1977, ‘Husserl’s Conception of a Purely Logical Grammar’, in R. Soko-lowski (ed.), Readings on Edmund Husserl’s Logical Investigations, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, pp. 128–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J.: 2000, ‘Hermann Weyl on Intuition and the Continuum’, Philosophia Mathematica 8(3), 259–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beisswanger, P.: 1965, ‘Die Phases in Hermann Weyls Beurteilung der Mathematik’, Mathematisch-Physicalische Semesterberichte New Series 12, 132–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chihara, C.: 1973, Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle, Cornell University Press, Ithaca.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodge, C. W.: 1969, Sets, Logic and Numbers, Prindle, Weber & Schmidt, Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A.: 1952, ‘The Foundation of the General Theory of Relativity’, in W. Perrett and G. B. Jeffrey (1952), pp. 111–164.

  • Feist, R.: 2000, ‘Edmund Husserl as Part of the Göttingen Scientific Tradition’, Science et Esprit 52, 193–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosado Haddock, G. E.: 1987, ‘Husserl’s Epistemology of Mathematics and the Foundation of Platonism in Mathematics’, Husserl Studies4, 81–102.

  • Husserl, E.: 1970, Logical Investigations, J. N. Findlay (trans.), 2nd edn, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E.: 1983, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: First Book, F. Kersten (trans.), Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  • da Silva, J. J.: 1997, ‘Husserl’s Phenomenology and Weyl’s Predicativism’, Synthese 110, 277–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerszberg, P.: 1986, ‘Sur La Physique et la Phénoménologie De Hermann Weyl’, Etudes Phénoménologiques 3, 2–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerszberg, P.: 1989, The Invented Universe: The Einstein-DeSitter Controversy (1916-1917) and the Rise of Relativistic Cosmology, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, D.: 1970, Reason and Evidence in Husserl’s Phenomenology, Northwestern University Press, Evaston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P.: 1998, From Brouwer to Hilbert: The Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in the 1920s, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minkowski, H.: 1952, ‘Space and Time, in W. Perrett and G. B. Jeffrey (1952), pp. 75–91.

  • Monna, A. F.: 1975, Dirichlet’s Principle: A Mathematical Study of Errors and its Influence on the Development of Analysis, Utrecht, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K.: 1992, ‘Perception’, in B. Smith and D. W. Smith (1992), pp. 168–238.

  • Perrett, W. and G. B. Jeffrey: 1952, The Principle of Relativity: A Collection of Original Memoirs on the Special and General Theory of Relativity, Dover Publications, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Philipse, H.: 1992, ‘Transcendental Idealism’, in B. Smith and D. W. Smith (1992), pp. 239–322.

  • Poincaré, H.: 1908, ‘Science et MĆéhode’, in E. Flammarion (ed.), Bibliotheque de Philosophie scientifique, Paris.

  • Poincaré, H.: 1910, ‘Ñber transfinite Zahlen’, in Mathematische Vorlesungen an der Universität Göttingen: IV, Teubner, Leipzig and Berlin, pp. 45–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H.: 1917, ‘Derniéres Pensées’, in E. Flammarion (ed.), Bibliotheque de Philo-sophie scientifique, Paris.

  • Ramsey, F.: 1990, ‘Mathematical Logic’, in D. H. Mellor (ed.), Philosophical Papers, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 225–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryckman, T.: 1994, ‘Weyl, Reichenbach and the Epistemology of Geometry’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 6, 831–870.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M.: 1918, Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, Springer Verlag, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. and D. W. Smith: 1992, The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, R.: 1974, Husserlian Meditations, Northwestern University Press, Evaston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tieszen, R.: 2000, ‘The Philosophical Background of Weyl’s Mathematical Constructivism’, Philosophical Mathematica 8(3), 274–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Dalen, D.: 1984, ‘Four Letters from Edmund Husserl to Hermann Weyl’, Husserl Studies I, 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Dalen, D.: 1995, ‘Hermann Weyl’s Intuitionistic Mathematics’, Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1, 145–169

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1910, ‘Ñber die Definitionen der mathematischen Grundbegriffe’, in H. Weyl (1968), Vol. 2, pp. 299–304.

  • Weyl, H.: 1921, ‘Ñber die Physikalischen Grundlagen der erweiterten RelativitĎtstheorie’, in H. Weyl (1968), Vol. 2, pp. 229–236.

  • Weyl, H.: 1923, ‘Review of Schlick’s Allgemeine Erkenntislehre’, Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der Mathematik 46, 59–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1932, The Open World: Three Lectures on the Metaphysical Implications of Science, Yale University Press, New Haven.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1952, Space-Time-Matter, 4th edn, H. Brose (trans.), Dover, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1955a, ‘Erkenntnis und Besinnung (Ein Lebensr Ąckblick)’, Studia Philosophica 15, 153–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1955b, The Concept of a Riemann Surface, Addison-Wesley, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1963, Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science, Antheum, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1968, in K. Chandrasekharan (ed.), Gesammelte Abhandlungen, 4 Vols., Springer Verlag, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H.: 1985, ‘Axiomatic Versus Constructive Procedures in Mathematics’, in T. Tonietti (ed.), The Mathematical Intelligencer 4, 10–17, 38.

  • Weyl, H.: 1987, The Continuum: A Critical Examination of the Foundations of Analysis, in S. Pollard and T. Bole (trans.), The Thomas Jefferson Press, Kirksville.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willard, D.: 1992, ‘Knowledge’, in B. Smith and D. W. Smith (1992), pp. 138–167.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Feist, R. Weyl’s Appropriation of Husserl’s and Poincar“s Thought. Synthese 132, 273–301 (2002). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1020370823738

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1020370823738

Keywords

Navigation