Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy

, Volume 3, Issue 2, pp 109–116 | Cite as

Evolutionary biology and the concept of disease

  • Anne Gammelgaard
Article

Abstract

In recent years, an increasing number of medical books and papers attempting to analyse the concepts of health and disease from the perspective of evolutionary biology have been published (Eaton etal., 1993; Ewald, 1993; Harrison, 1993; Nesse and Williams, 1995; Profet, 1991; Rose, 1991; Temple and Burkitt, 1994).

This paper introduces the evolutionary approach to health and disease in an attempt to illuminate the premisses and the framework of Darwinian medicine. My primary aim is to analyse to what extent evolutionary theory provides for a biological definition of the concept of disease. This analysis reveals some important differences between functional explanations in the field of evolutionary biology and functional explanations in the field of medicine. Moreover, I shall argue that the biological functions relevant to the health of an organism cannot be determined on the basis of evolutionary theory. Accordingly, it seems that Darwinian medicine does not provide for the definition of a biological concept of disease. Still,Darwinian medicine may suggest why we are susceptible to certain diseases; it might also prove a suggestive heuristic on the basis of which new hypotheses concerning relevant treatments of various diseases might be advanced.

concept of disease Darwinian medicine evolutionary biology functional explanations 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Allen, C., M. Bekoff and G. Lauder (eds.): 1998, Nature's Purposes: Analysis of Function and Design in Biology. Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
  2. Boorse, C.: 1975, 'On the distinction between disease and illness', Philosophy and Public Affairs 5, pp. 49-68.Google Scholar
  3. Boorse, C.: 1976a, 'Wright on functions', Philos. Rev. 85, pp. 70-86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Boorse, C.: 1976b, 'What a theory of mental health should be', J.Theory of Social Behaviour 6, pp. 61-84.Google Scholar
  5. Boorse, C.: 1977, 'Health as a theoretical concept', Philos. Sci. 44, pp. 542-573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Boorse, C.: 1997, 'A Rebuttal on Health', in J.M. Humber and R.F. Almeder (eds.), What is Disease? Totowa: Humana Press.Google Scholar
  7. Brandon, R.N. and R.M. Burian (eds.): 1984, Genes, Organisms, Populations: Controversies over the Units of Selection. Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
  8. Brown, W.M.: 1985, 'On defining disease', J. Med. Phil. 10, pp. 311-328.Google Scholar
  9. Cavalier-Smith, T.: 1980, 'How selfish is DNA?', Nature 285, pp. 617-618.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cummins, R.: 1975, 'Functional analysis', J. Philos. 72, pp. 741-764.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Dawkins, R.: 1976, The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Eaton, S.B., M.C. Pike, R.V. Short, N.C. Lee, J. Trussel and R.A. Hatcher et al.: 1993, 'Women's reproductive cancers in evolutionary context', The Quarterly Review of Biology 69, pp. 353-367.Google Scholar
  13. Engelhardt, H.T. Jr.: 1986, The Foundations of Bioethics. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Ewald, P.W.: 1993, Evolution of Infectious Disease. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Gordeuk, V.R., P.E. Thuma, G.M. Brittenham, S. Zulu, G. Simwanza and A. Mhangu et al.: 1992a, 'Iron chelation with desferrioxamine B in adults with asymptotic Plasmodium falciparum parasitemia', Blood 79, pp. 308-312.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  16. Gordeuk, V.R., P.E. Thuma, G.M. Brittenham, C. McLaren, D. Parry and A. Backenstose et al.: 1992b, 'Effect of iron chelation therapy on recovery from deep coma in children with cerebral malaria', N. Eng. Jour. Med. 327, pp. 1473-1477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Harrison, G.A.S. (ed.): 1993, Human Adaptation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Kovács, J.: 1998, 'The concept of health and disease', Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1, pp. 31-39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Margolis, J.: 1976, 'The concept of disease', J. Med. Philos. 1, pp. 238-255.Google Scholar
  20. Miller, J.F., J.J. Mekalanos and S. Falkow: 1989, 'Coordinate regulation and sensory transduction in the control of bacterial virulence', Science 243, pp. 916-922.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  21. Millikan, R.G.: 1989, 'In defense of proper functions', Philos. Sci. 56, pp. 288-302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Nesse, R.M. and G.C. Williams: 1995, Evolution and Healing: The New Science of Darwinian Medicine. London: Phoenix.Google Scholar
  23. Orgel, L.E., F.H.C. Crick and C. Sapienza: 1980, 'Selfish DNA', Nature 288, pp. 645-646.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Preston, B.: 1998, 'Why is a wing like a spoon? A pluralist theory of function', The Journal of Philosophy XCV(5), pp. 215-254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Profet, M.: 1991, 'The Function of Allergy: Immunological defense against toxins', The Quarterly Review of Biology 6, pp. 23-62.Google Scholar
  26. Reznek, L.: 1987, The Nature of Disease. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  27. Reznik, D.: 1997, 'Adaptationism: hypothesis or heuristic?', Biology and Philosophy 12, pp. 39-50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Rose, M.R.: 1991, Evolutionary Biology of Aging. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Rottschaefer, W.A.: 1997, 'Adaptational functional ascriptions in evolutionary biology: a critique of Schaffner's views', Philos. Sci. 64, pp. 698-713.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Schaffner, K.F.: 1993, Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  31. Sober, E.: 1991, 'Organisms, individuals, and the units of selection', in A. Tauber (ed.), Organism and the Origins of Self. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 275-296.Google Scholar
  32. Sober, E.: 1993, Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Sober, E. and D.S. Wilson: 1994, 'A critical review of philosophical work on the unit of selection problem', Philos. Sci. 61, pp. 534-555.Google Scholar
  34. Stove, D.: 1995, Darwinian Fairytales. Aldershot: Avebury.Google Scholar
  35. Temple, N.J. and D.P. Burkitt (eds.): 1994, Western Diseases: Their Prevention and Reversibility. New Jersey: Humana Press.Google Scholar
  36. Wimsatt, W.: 1972, 'Teleology and the logical structure of function statements', Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 3, pp. 1-80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Wright, L.: 1973, 'Functions', Philos. Rev. 82, pp. 139-168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2000

Authors and Affiliations

  • Anne Gammelgaard
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of Medical Philosophy and Clinical Theory, Institute of Public Health, Faculty of Health SciencesUniversity of CopenhagenCopenhagen

Personalised recommendations