Explaining the Identifiable Victim Effect

Abstract

It is widely believed that people are willing to expend greater resources to save the lives of identified victims than to save equal numbers of unidentified or statistical victims. There are many possible causes of this disparity which have not been enumerated previously or tested empirically. We discuss four possible causes of the identifiable victim effect and present the results of two studies which indicate that the most important cause of the disparity in treatment of identifiable and statistical lives is that, for identifiable victims, a high proportion of those at risk can be saved.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

References

  1. Batson, C. Daniel, et al. (1991). “Empathic joy and the empathy-altruism hypothesis.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 62, 413–26.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bullard, Robert D. (1993). Confronting Environmental Racism: Voices from the Grassroots. Boston: South End Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Calabresi, Guido, and Philip Bobbitt (1978). Tragic Choices. New York: W.W. Norton and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cialdini, Robert B., et al. (1987). “Empathy-based helping: is it selflessly or selfishly motivated?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52, 749–58.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cohen, M, J. Y. Jaffray, and T. Said (1987). “Experimental comparison of individual behavior under risk and under uncertainty for gains and for losses,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 39, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cushman, John H. Jr. (1994). “Clinton to Order Effort to Make Pollution Fairer,” The NewYork Times, February 10, page A1.

  7. Douglas, Mary (1992). Risk and Blame: Essays in Cultural Theory. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Egan, Timothy (1994). “A 3-Strike Law Shows It's Not as Simple as it Seems,” The New York Times, February 15, p. A1.

  9. Gibbard, Allan (1986). “Risk and Value,” in Douglas MacLean (Ed.), Values at Risk. New Jersey: Rowan and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Gillette, Clayton P., and Thomas D. Hopkins (1988). Federal Agency Valuations of Human Life. Administrative Conference of the United States, Report for Recommendation 88–7.

  11. Glover, Jonathan (1977). Causing Death and Saving Lives. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Goodman, Walter (1993). “TV, by its very nature, can stack the deck,” The New York Times, September 13, p. C20.

  13. Gore, Al (1992). Earth in the Balance: Ecology and the Human Spirit. New York: Plume.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Horowitz, John K. and Richard T. Carson (1993). “Baseline risk and Preference for Reductions in Risk to Life.” Risk Analysis 13 (2), 457–462.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Keeney, Ralph L. (1995). “Understanding Life-Threatening Risks,” Risk Analysis 15 (6).

  16. Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk.” Econometrica 47(2).

  17. Latané, Bibb, and John M. Darley (1970). The Unresponsive Bystander: Why doesn't he help?. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Linden, Eugene (1988). “Helping Out Putu, Siku and Kanik,” Time Magazine, pp. 76–77. October 31.

  19. MacLean, Douglas (1986). “Social Values and the Distribution of Risk,” in Douglas MacLean (Ed.), Values at Risk. New Jersey: Rowan and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  20. National Research Council (1989). Improving Risk Communication. Washington DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Nisbett, Richard and Lee Ross (1980). Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  22. People Weekly (1987). “America's heart goes out to Baby Jessica.” Volume 28:18. November 2.

  23. People Weekly (1990). Volume 33:15. April 16.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Piliavin, Jane A., et al. (1981). Emergency Intervention. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Piliavin, Irving M., Judith Rodin, and Jane A. Piliavin (1969). “Good samaritanism: an underground phenomenon?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 13, 289–299.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Massachussetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Rawls, John (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Raynor, Steve (1992). “Cultural Theory and Risk Analysis,” In Seldon Krimsky and Dominic Golding (Eds.), Social Theories of Risk. Connecticut: Praeger Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Redelmeier, Donald A. and Amos Tversky (1990). “Occasional Note: Discrepancy Between Medical Decisions for Individual Patients and for Groups,” The New England Journal of Medicine, April 19.

  30. Ritov, Ilana, and Jonathan Baron (1990). “Reluctance to Vaccinate: Omission Bias and Ambiguity,” Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 3, 263–277.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Schelling, T. C. (1968). “The Life You Save May Be Your Own,” in Samuel Chase (Ed.), Problems in Public Expenditure Analysis. Washington DC: The Brookings Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Shotland, R. Lance (1983). “What's wrong with helping behavior research? Only the independent and dependent variables.” Academic Psychology Bulletin 5, 339–350.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Shrader-Frechette, K. S. (1991). Risk and Rationality: Philosophical Foundations for Populist Reforms. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Skelton, George (1993). “A Father's Crusade Born From Pain,” The Los Angeles Times, December 9, p. A3.

  35. Slovic, P., B. Fischhoff, and S. Lichtenstein. (1980). “Facts and Fears: Understanding Perceived Risk,” In Richard C. Schwing and Walther A. Albers, Jr. (Eds.), Societal Risk Assessment: How Safe is Safe Enough? New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Taylor, S. E. and S. C. Thompson (1982). “Stalking the elusive ‘vividness’ effect.” Psychological Review 89, 155–181.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Toufexis, Anastasia (1993). “The Ultimate Choice.” Time Magazine, pp. 43–44. August 31.

  38. Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman (1981). “The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice,” Science 211, 243–258.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman (1986). “Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions,” Journal of Business 59 (4), part 2.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Variety (1989). “TV Reviews—Network: Everybody's Baby,” Volume 335:7, May 31.

  41. Viscusi, W. Kip and William N. Evans (1990). “Utility Functions That Depend on Health Status: Estimates and Economic Implications,” The American Economic Review 80 (3), 353–374.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Viscusi, W. Kip (1992). Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Weinstein, Milton C., Donald S. Shepard, and Joseph S. Pliskin (1980). “The Economic Value of Changing Mortality Probabilities: A Decision-Theoretic Approach,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 94, 373–396.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Whipple, Chris (1992). “Inconsistent Values in Risk Management” in Seldon Krimsky and Dominic Golding (Eds.), Social Theories of Risk. Connecticut: Praeger Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Cite this article

JENNI, K., LOEWENSTEIN, G. Explaining the Identifiable Victim Effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 14, 235–257 (1997). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1007740225484

Download citation

  • value of life
  • identifiable victims