Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 118, Issue 1, pp 89–104 | Cite as

Representation and self-awareness in intentional agents

  • Ingar Brinck
  • Peter Gärdenfors
Article

Abstract

Several conditions for being an intrinsically intentional agent are put forward. On a first level of intentionality the agent has representations. Two kinds are described: cued and detached. An agent with both kinds is able to represent both what is prompted by the context and what is absent from it. An intermediate level of intentionality is achieved by having an inner world, that is, a coherent system of detached representations that model the world. The inner world is used, e.g., for conditional and counterfactual thinking. Contextual or indexical representations are necessary in order that the inner world relates to the actual external world and thus can be used as a basis for action. To have full-blown intentionality, the agent should also have a detached self-awareness, that is, be able to entertain self-representations that are independent of the context.

Keywords

Intermediate Level External World Indexical Representation Coherent System Intentional Agent 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Brinck, I.: 1997, The Indexical “I”, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
  2. Campbell, J.: 1994, Past, Space, and Self, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  3. Campbell, J.: 1995, ‘The Body Image and Self-Consciousness’, in J. L. BermÚdez, A. Marcel, N. Eilan (eds.), The Body and the Self, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  4. Clark, A.: 1997, Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  5. Craik, K.: 1943, The Nature of Explanation, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  6. Deacon, T.: 1996, ‘Prefrontal Cortex and Symbol Learning: Why a Brain Capable of Language Evolved Only Once’, in B. M. Velichkovsky and D. M. Rumbaugh (eds.), Communicating Meaning: The Evolution and Development of Language, Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ, pp. 103–138.Google Scholar
  7. Dennett, D.: 1978, Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  8. Dennett, D.: 1981, ‘True Believers: The Intentional Strategy and Why It Works’, in A. F. Heath (ed.), Scientific Explanation, Clarendon Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
  9. Dennett, D.: 1983, ‘Intentional Systems in Cognitive Ethology: The “Panglossian Paradigm” Defended’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6, 343–390.Google Scholar
  10. Dennett, D.: 1991, Consciousness Explained, Little, Brown and Company, Boston, MA.Google Scholar
  11. Fodor, J. A.: 1986, ‘Why Paramecia Don't have Mental Representations’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10, 3–23.Google Scholar
  12. Gärdenfors, P.: 1996a, ‘Cued and Detached Representations in Animal Cognition’, Behavioural Processes 36, 263–273.Google Scholar
  13. Gärdenfors, P.: 1996b, ‘Language and the Evolution of Cognition’, in V. Rialle and D. Fisette (eds.), Penser l'esprit: Des Sciences de la Cognition à une Philosophie Cognitive, Presses Universitaires de Grenoble, Grenoble, pp. 151–172.Google Scholar
  14. Gärdenfors, P.: 1997, ‘The Role of Memory in Planning and Pretense’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20, 24–25.Google Scholar
  15. Glenberg A. M.: 1997, ‘What Memory Is For’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20, 1–19.Google Scholar
  16. Gopnik, M.: 1982, ‘Some Distinctions Among Representations’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5, 378–379.Google Scholar
  17. Gopnik, A.: 1993, ‘How we Know our Minds: The Illusion of First-Person Knowledge of Intentionality’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16, 1–14.Google Scholar
  18. Gulz, A.: 1991, The Planning of Action as a Cognitive and Biological Phenomenon, Lund University Cognitive Studies 2, Lund.Google Scholar
  19. Jeannerod, M.: 1994, ‘The Representing Brain, Neural Correlates of Motor Intention and Imagery’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17, 187–202.Google Scholar
  20. Lachman, R. and J. L. Lachman: 1982, ‘Memory Representations in Animals: Some Metatheoretical Issues’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5, 380–381.Google Scholar
  21. Luria, A. R.: 1973, The Working Brain, Basic Books, New York.Google Scholar
  22. Merleau-Ponty, M.: 1962, Phenomenology of Perception, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.Google Scholar
  23. Pallbo, R.: 1997, Mind in Motion: The Utilization of Noise in the Cognitive Process, Lund University Cognitive Studies 57, Lund.Google Scholar
  24. Piaget, J. and B. Inhelder: 1956, The Child's Conception of Space, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.Google Scholar
  25. Reuter,M.: 1999, ‘Merleau-Ponty's Notion of Pre-Reflective Intentionality’, Synthese 118, 69–88 (this issue).Google Scholar
  26. Roitblat, H. L.: 1982, ‘The Meaning of Representation in Animal Memory’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5, 353–372.Google Scholar
  27. Sjölander, S.: 1993, ‘Some Cognitive Breakthroughs in the Evolution of Cognition and Consciousness, and their Impact on the Biology of Language’, Evolution and Cognition 3, 1–10.Google Scholar
  28. Tolman, E. C.: 1948, ‘Cognitive Maps in Rats and Men’, Psychological Review 55, 189–208.Google Scholar
  29. Von Uexküll, J.: 1985, ‘Environment and Inner World of Animals’, in G. M. Burghardt (ed.), Foundations of Comparative Ethology, Van Nostrand Reinhold Company, New York, pp. 222–245.Google Scholar
  30. Vauclair, J.: 1987, ‘A Comparative Approach to Cognitive Mapping’, in P. Ellen and C. Thinus-Blanc (eds.), Cognitive Processes and Spatial Orientation in Animal and Man: Volume I Experimental Animal Psychology and Ethology, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht, pp. 89–96.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 1999

Authors and Affiliations

  • Ingar Brinck
    • 1
  • Peter Gärdenfors
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyLund UniversityLundSweden

Personalised recommendations