Journal of Medical Humanities

, Volume 22, Issue 2, pp 95–114 | Cite as

Responsibility for Health and Blaming Victims

  • Mike W. Martin
Article

Abstract

If we are responsible for taking care of our health, are we blameworthy when we become sick because we failed to meet that responsibility? Or is it immoral to blame the victim of sickness? A moral perspective that is sensitive to therapeutic concerns will downplay blame, but banishing all blame is neither feasible nor desirable. We need to understand the ambiguities surrounding moral responsibility in four contexts: (1) preventing sickness, (2) assigning financial liabilities for health care costs, (3) giving meaning to human suffering, and (4) interacting with health care professionals. We also need to distinguish different kinds of blame, explore the interplay of justice and compassion in avoiding unjustified blaming of victims, and work toward a unified moral-therapeutic perspective that encourages individuals to accept responsibility while avoiding destructive forms of blaming.

blaming victims compassion illness justice responsibility for health 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Alexander, L. (1980). The double-bind between dialysis patients and their health practitioners. In L.Eisenberg & A. Kleinman (<nt>Eds.</nt>), The relevance of social science for medicine (pp. 307–329).Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  2. Allegrante, J. P., & Green, L. W. (1981). When health policy becomes victim blaming. New England Journal of Medicine, 305, 1528–1529.Google Scholar
  3. Arras, J. (1997) Nice story, but so what?: Narrative and justification in ethics. In H. L. Nelson (<nt>Ed.</nt>), Stories and their limits: Narrative approaches to bioethics (pp. 65–90). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  4. Bellah, R., Madsen, R., Sullivan, W. M., Swidler, A., & Tipton, S. M. (1985). Habits of the heart: Individualism and commitment in American life. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  5. Broyard, A. (1992). Intoxicated by my illness. New York: Fawcett Columbine.Google Scholar
  6. Butler, J. (1964). Upon resentment. In W. R. Matthews (<nt>Eds.</nt>), Fifteen sermons (pp. 120–132). London: G. Bell.Google Scholar
  7. Butler, S. (1960). Erewhon. New York: New American Library.Google Scholar
  8. Callahan, D. (1998). False hopes: Why America's quest for perfect health is a recipe for failure. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
  9. Card, C. (1996). The unnatural lottery: Character and moral luck. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Cassell, E. J. (1991). The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. New York: Oxford University.Google Scholar
  11. Crawford, R. (1997). Individual responsibility and health politics. In P. Conrad (<nt>Ed.</nt>), The sociology of health and illness: Critical perspectives (5th ed., pp. 393–401). New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
  12. Darwall, S. L. (1983). Impartial reason. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Duff, K. (1993). The alchemy of illness. New York: Bell Tower.Google Scholar
  14. Dworkin, G. (1981). Taking risks, assessing responsibility. The Hastings Center Report, 11, 26–31.Google Scholar
  15. Fingarette, H. (1963). The self in transformation. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  16. Fitzgibbons, R. (1998). Anger and the healing power of forgiveness: A psychiatrist's view. In R. D. Enright & J. North (<nt>Eds.</nt>), Exploring forgiveness (pp. 63–74). Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  17. Frank, A. (1991). At the will of the body: Reflections on illness. New York: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
  18. Frank, A. (1995). The wounded storyteller: Body, illness, and ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago.Google Scholar
  19. Frank, A. (1997). Enacting illness stories. In H. L. Nelson (<nt>Ed.</nt>), Stories and their limits: Narrative approaches to bioethics (pp. 31–49). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  20. Freud, S. (1961). Civilization and its discontents (J. Strachey, Trans.). New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
  21. Gilligan, J. (1997). Violence: Reflections on a national epidemic. New York: Vintage.Google Scholar
  22. Gordon, L. (1997). Teenage pregnancy and out-of-wedlock birth: Morals, moralism, experts. In A. M. Brandt & P. Rozin (<nt>Eds.</nt>), Morality and health (pp. 251–271). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  23. Houston, B. (1992). In praise of blame. Hypatia, 7, 128–147.Google Scholar
  24. Jaeger, M. (1998). The power and reality of forgiveness: Forgiving the murderer of one's child. In R. D. Enright & J. North (<nt>Eds.</nt>), Exploring forgiveness (pp. 9–14). Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  25. Janoff-Bulman, R. (1979). Characterological versus behavioral self-blame: Inquiries into depression and rape. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 1798–1809.Google Scholar
  26. Kant, I. (1963). Lectures on ethics. (L. Infield, Trans.). New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
  27. Kass, L. R. (1975). Regarding the end of medicine and the pursuit of health. Public Interest, 40, 11–42.Google Scholar
  28. Kleinman, A. (1988). The illness narratives: Suffering, healing, and the human condition. New York: BasicBooks.Google Scholar
  29. Knowles, J. H. (1977). The responsibility of the individual. Daedelus, 106, 57–80.Google Scholar
  30. Lamb, S. (1996). The trouble with blame: Victims, perpetrators, and responsibility. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.Google Scholar
  31. Leichter, H.M. (1997). Lifestyle correctness and the new secular morality. In A.M. Brandt & P. Rozin (<nt>Eds.</nt>), Morality and health (pp. 359–378). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  32. Lorde, A. (1980). The cancer journals. San Francisco: Aunt Lute Books.Google Scholar
  33. Martin, M. W. (1999a). Alcoholism as sickness and wrongdoing. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 29, 109–131.Google Scholar
  34. Martin, M. W. (1999b). Good fortune obligates: Gratitude, philanthropy, and colonialism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 37, 57–75.Google Scholar
  35. Martin, M.W. (2000a). Meaningful work: Rethinking professional ethics.NewYork: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Martin, M. W. (2000b). Moral health: Responsibility in therapeutic culture. Journal of Value Inquiry, 34, 27–43.Google Scholar
  37. McCullough, M. E., Pargament, K. I., & Thoresen, C. E. (2000). Forgiveness: Theory, research, and practice. New York: The Guilford Press.Google Scholar
  38. McKegney, F. P., & Lange, P. (1971). The decision to no longer live on chronic hemodialysis. American Journal of Psychiatry, 128, 267–274.Google Scholar
  39. Morris, D. B. (1991). The culture of pain. Berkeley, CA: University of California.Google Scholar
  40. Moyers, B. (1993). Healing the mind. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
  41. Nietzsche, F. (1998). On the genealogy of morality, (M. Clark & A. J. Swensen, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
  42. Parsons, T. (1979). Definitions of health and illness in the light of American values and social structure. In E. G. Jaco (<nt>ed.</nt>), Patients, physicians and illness (3rd ed., pp. 120–144). London: Free Press.Google Scholar
  43. Pellegrino, E. D., & Thomasma, D. C. (1993). The virtues of medical practice. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Pincoffs, E. L. (1986). Quandaries and virtues. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.Google Scholar
  45. Poirier, S. (1996). Expressing illness: Review essay of Arthur W. Frank, The wounded storyteller, Medical Humanities Review, 10, 74–79.Google Scholar
  46. Reiser, S. J. (1985). Responsibility for personal health: A historical perspective. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 10, 7–17.Google Scholar
  47. Ryan, W. (1976). Blaming the victim (<nt>Rev. ed.</nt>). New York: Vintage.Google Scholar
  48. Schoeman, F. (1991). Alcohol addiction and responsibility. In M. I. Bockover (<nt>Ed.</nt>), Rules, rituals, and responsibility (pp. 11–36). La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  49. Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., & Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of morality (autonomy, community, divinity) and the “big three” explanations of suffering. In A. M. Brandt & P. Rozin (<nt>Eds.</nt>), Morality and health (pp. 119–169). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  50. Schweitzer, A. (1990). Out of my life and thought, (A.B. Lemke, Trans.). New York: Henry Holt.Google Scholar
  51. Sontag, S. (1990). Illness as metaphor and AIDS and its metaphors. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
  52. Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 187–211.Google Scholar
  53. Thomas, K. (1997). Health and morality in early modern England. In A. M. Brandt & P. Rozin (<nt>Eds.</nt>), Morality and health (pp. 15–34). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  54. Veatch, R. M. (2000). The basics of bioethics. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  55. Wachtel, P. L. (1999). Race in the mind of America. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  56. Wikler, D. (1987). Who should be blamed for being sick? Health Education Quarterly, 14, 11–25.Google Scholar
  57. Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Human Sciences Press, Inc. 2001

Authors and Affiliations

  • Mike W. Martin
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyChapman UniversityOrange

Personalised recommendations