Minds and Machines

, Volume 14, Issue 1, pp 101–117

Epistemic Value Theory and Information Ethics

  • Don Fallis
Article

Abstract

Three of the major issues in information ethics – intellectual property, speech regulation, and privacy – concern the morality of restricting people’s access to certain information. Consequently, policies in these areas have a significant impact on the amount and types of knowledge that people acquire. As a result, epistemic considerations are critical to the ethics of information policy decisions (cf. Mill, 1978 [1859]). The fact that information ethics is a part of the philosophy of information highlights this important connection with epistemology. In this paper, I illustrate how a value-theoretic approach to epistemology can help to clarify these major issues in information ethics. However, I also identify several open questions about epistemic values that need to be answered before we will be able to evaluate the epistemic consequences of many information policies.

epistemic value theory epistemology information ethics intellectual property philosophy of information privacy social epistemology speech regulation 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Benn, S.I. (1984), ‘Privacy, Freedom and Respect for Persons’, in F.D. Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 223–244.Google Scholar
  2. Broome, J. (1991), Weighting Goods, Cambridge: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  3. Broome, J. (1994), ‘Discounting the Future’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 23, pp. 128–156.Google Scholar
  4. Descartes, R. (1988), Selected Philosophical Writings, New York: Cambridge.Google Scholar
  5. DePaul, M.R. (2001), ‘Value Monism in Epistemology’, in M. Steup, ed., Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 170–183.Google Scholar
  6. Driver, J. (1999), ‘Modesty and Ignorance’, Ethics 109, pp. 827–834.Google Scholar
  7. Fallis, D. (2002), ‘Introduction: Social Epistemology and Information Science’, Social Epistemology 16, pp. 1–4.Google Scholar
  8. Faltings, G. (1995), ‘The Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem by R. Taylor and A.Wiles’, Notices of the American Mathematical Society 42, pp. 743–746.Google Scholar
  9. Field, H. (1982), ‘Realism and Relativism’, Journal of Philosophy 79, pp. 553–567.Google Scholar
  10. Floridi, L. (2002), ‘What Is the Philosophy of Information?’, Metaphilosophy 33, pp. 123–145.Google Scholar
  11. Floridi, L. (forthcoming), ‘Open Problems in the Philosophy of Information’, Metaphilosophy.Google Scholar
  12. Floridi, L. and Sanders, J.W. (2002), ‘Mapping the Foundationalist Debate in Computer Ethics’, Ethics and Information Technology 4, pp. 1–9.Google Scholar
  13. Frické, M., Mathiesen, K. and Fallis, D. (2002), ‘The Ethical Presuppositions Behind the Library Bill of Rights’, Library Quarterly 70, pp. 468–491.Google Scholar
  14. Garoogian, R. (1991), ‘Librarian/Patron Confidentiality: An Ethical Challenge’, Library Trends 40, pp. 216–233Google Scholar
  15. Goldman, A.I. (1999), Knowledge in a Social World, New York; Oxford.Google Scholar
  16. Goldman, A.I. (2000), ‘Replies to Reviews of Knowledge in a Social World’, Social Epistemology 14, pp. 317–333.Google Scholar
  17. Hardwig, J. (1985), ‘Epistemic Dependence’, Journal of Philosophy 82, pp. 335–349.Google Scholar
  18. Harsanyi, J.C. (1977), Rational Behaviour and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Hettinger, E.C. (1989), ‘Justifying Intellectual Property’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 18, pp. 31–52.Google Scholar
  20. Hoffmann, G.M. (2001), Copyright in Cyberspace, New York: Neal-Schuman.Google Scholar
  21. Hume, D. (1977), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  22. Hutchins, E. (1995), Cognition in the Wild, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. James, W. (1979), The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Kawall, J. (2002), ‘Other-Regarding Epistemic Virtues’, Ratio 15, pp. 257–275.Google Scholar
  25. Kirkwood, C.W. (1997), Strategic Decision Making, Belmont, CA: Duxbury.Google Scholar
  26. Kitcher, P. (2001), ‘Knowledge and Tradition’, Philosophy Topics 29, pp. 251–270.Google Scholar
  27. Lehrer, K. (1975), ‘Reason and Consistency’, in K. Lehrer, ed., Analysis and Metaphysics, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 57–74.Google Scholar
  28. Levi, I. (1962), ‘On the Serious of Mistakes’, Philosophy of Science 29, pp. 47–65.Google Scholar
  29. Maher, P. (1993), Betting on Theories, New York: Cambridge.Google Scholar
  30. McDowell, A. (2002), ‘Trust and Information: The Role of Trust in the Social Epistemology of Information Science’, Social Epistemology 16, pp. 51–63.Google Scholar
  31. Mill, J.S. (1978), On Liberty, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  32. Moor, J.H. (1985), ‘What Is Computer Ethics?’, Metaphilosophy 16, pp. 266–275.Google Scholar
  33. Paterson, R.W.K. (1979), ‘Towards and Axiology of Knowledge’, Journal of Philosophy of Education 13, pp. 91–100.Google Scholar
  34. Plato (1961), Plato: The Collected Dialogues, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Popper, K. (1972), Objective Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Riggs, W.D. (2002), ‘Reliability and the Value of Knowledge’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, pp. 79–96.Google Scholar
  38. Riggs, W.D. (2003), ‘Balancing Our Epistemic Ends’, Nous 37, pp. 342–352.Google Scholar
  39. Roger, T.J. (2003), Anarchist's Cookbook, http://isuisse.ifrance.com/emmaf/indanarcook.html.Google Scholar
  40. Ross, W.D. (1930), The Right and the Good, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Sidgwick, H. (1874), The Methods of Ethics, Chicago: University of Chicago.Google Scholar
  42. Spinello, R.A. (1995), Ethical Aspects of Information Technology, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  43. Tavani, H.T. and Grodzinsky, F.S. (2002), ‘Cyberstalking, Personal Privacy, and Moral Responsibility’, Ethics and Information Technology 4, pp. 123–132.Google Scholar
  44. Zagzebski, L. (2003), ‘The Search for the Source of Epistemic Good’, Metaphilosophy 34, pp. 12–28.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2004

Authors and Affiliations

  • Don Fallis
    • 1
  1. 1.School of Information ResourcesUniversity of ArizonaTucsonUSA

Personalised recommendations