Philosophical Studies

, Volume 115, Issue 1, pp 1–31 | Cite as

What Good are Counterexamples?

  • Brian Weatherson

Abstract

Intuitively, Gettier cases are instances of justified true beliefsthat are not cases of knowledge. Should we therefore conclude thatknowledge is not justified true belief? Only if we have reason totrust intuition here. But intuitions are unreliable in a wide rangeof cases. And it can be argued that the Gettier intuitions have agreater resemblance to unreliable intuitions than to reliableintuitions. What’s distinctive about the faulty intuitions, Iargue, is that respecting them would mean abandoning a simple,systematic and largely successful theory in favour of a complicated,disjunctive and idiosyncratic theory. So maybe respecting theGettier intuitions was the wrong reaction, we should instead havebeen explaining why we are all so easily misled by these kinds ofcases.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Armstrong, D.M. (1978): Universals and Scientific Realism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bealer, G. (1998): ‘Intuition and the Autonomy of Philosophy’, in M. DePaul and W. Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition (pp. 201–240), Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  3. Cummins, R. (1998): ‘Reflection on Reflective Equilibrium’, in M. DePaul and W. Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition (pp. 113–128), Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  4. DePaul, M. and Ramsey, W. (1998): Rethinking Intuition. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  5. DeRose, K. (1996): ‘Knowledge, Assertion and Lotteries’, Philosophical Review 74, 568–579.Google Scholar
  6. Field, H. (1973): ‘Theory Change and the Indeterminacy of Reference’, Journal of Philosophy 70, 462–481.Google Scholar
  7. Grice, H.P. (1989): Studies in the Way of Words, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Horowitz, T. (1998): ‘Philosophical Intuitions and Psychological Theory’, Ethics 108, 367–385.Google Scholar
  9. Horwich, P. (1999): Meaning, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Jackson, F. (1998): From Metaphysics to Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  11. Langton, R. and Lewis, D. (1998): ‘Defining ’Intrinsic, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58, 333–345.Google Scholar
  12. Langton, R. and Lewis, D. (2001): ‘Marshall and Parsons on ’Intrinsic, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, 353–355.Google Scholar
  13. Lewis, D. (1983): ‘New Work for a Theory of Universals’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61, 343–377.Google Scholar
  14. Lewis, D. (1984): ‘Putnam's Paradox’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62, 221–236.Google Scholar
  15. Lewis, D. (1992): ‘Meaning Without Use’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70, 106–110.Google Scholar
  16. Lewis, D. (2001): ‘Redefining ’Intrinsic, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, 381–398.Google Scholar
  17. Menzies, P. (1996): ‘Probabilistic Causation and the Pre-emption Problem’, Mind 105, 85–117.Google Scholar
  18. Nelkin, D. (2000): ‘The Lottery Paradox, Knowledge, and Rationality’, Philosophical Review 109, 373–409.Google Scholar
  19. Ramsey, W. (1998): ‘Prototypes and Conceptual Analysis’, in M. DePaul and W. Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition (pp. 161–177), Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  20. Rosch, E. and Mervis, C. (1975): ‘Family Resemblances: Studies in the Internal Structure of Categories’, Cognitive Science 8, 382–439.Google Scholar
  21. Ryle, G. (1950): The Concept of Mind, New York: Barnes and Noble.Google Scholar
  22. Shope, R. (1983): The Analysis of Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Sider, T. (2001): ‘Maximality and Intrinsic Properties’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, 357–364.Google Scholar
  24. Smith, M. (1994): The Moral Problem, London: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  25. Sosa, E. (1998): ‘Minimal Intuition’, in M. DePaul and W. Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition (pp. 257–269), Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  26. Stich, S. (1988): ‘Reflective Equilibrium,Analytic Epistemology and the Problem of Cognitive Diversity’, Synthese 74, 391–413.Google Scholar
  27. Stich, S. (1992): ‘What is a Theory of Mental Representation?’ Mind 101, 243–263.Google Scholar
  28. Tennant, N. (1992): Autologic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Unger, P. (1996): Living High and Letting Die, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Weinberg, J., Stich, S. and Nichols, S. (2001): ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions’, Philosophical Topics 29, 429–460.Google Scholar
  31. Williamson, T. (2000): Knowledge and Its Limits, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Wittgenstein, L. (1953): Philosophical Investigations, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2003

Authors and Affiliations

  • Brian Weatherson
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyBrown UniversityProvidenceUSA (E-mail

Personalised recommendations