Advertisement

Studia Logica

, Volume 73, Issue 2, pp 219–240 | Cite as

Belief Revision, Rational Choice and the Unity of Reason

  • Erik J. Olsson
Article

Abstract

Hans Rott has argued, most recently in his book Change, Choice and Inference, that certain formal correspondences between belief revision and rational choice have important philosophical implications, claiming that the former strongly indicate the unity of practical and theoretical reason as well as the primacy of practical reason. In this paper, I confront Rott's argument with three serious challenges. My conclusion is that, while Rott's work is indisputable as a formal achievement, the philosophical consequences he wants to draw are not forthcoming.

belief revision rational choice reason practical theoretical unity AGM 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. [1]
    AlchourrÓn, C., P. GÄrdenfors, and D. Makinson, ‘On the Logic of Theory Change: Partial Meet Contraction Functions and Their Associated Revision Functions’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 50:510–30, 1985.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. [2]
    BonJour, L., The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Harvard University Press, 1985.Google Scholar
  3. [3]
    Dalal, M., ‘Investigation Into a Theory of Knowledge Base Revision: Preliminary Report’, Seventh National Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI-88): 475–79, 1988.Google Scholar
  4. [4]
    Doyle, J., ‘Reason Maintenance and Belief Revision: Foundations vs. Coherence Theories’, in P. Gärdenfors (ed.), Belief Revision, Cambridge University Press: 29–51, 1992.Google Scholar
  5. [5]
    GÄrdenfors, P., ‘Group Decision Theory’, doctoral dissertation from the University of Lund, Sweden, Studentlitteratur, Lund, 1974.Google Scholar
  6. [6]
    GÄrdenfors, P., ‘Conditionals and Changes of Belief’, in I. Niiniluoto and R. Tuomela (eds), The Logic and Epistemology of Scientific Change, Acta Philosophica Fennica 30, Vol. 2–4, 1979.Google Scholar
  7. [7]
    GÄrdenfors, P., ‘Rights, Games and Social Choice’, Noûs 15:341–56, 1981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. [8]
    GÄrdenfors, P., Knowledge in Flux. Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States, MIT Press, 1988.Google Scholar
  9. [9]
    GÄrdenfors, P., ‘The Dynamics of Belief Systems: Foundations vs. Coherence Theories’, Révue Internationale de Philosophie 44:24–46, 1990.Google Scholar
  10. [10]
    GÄrdenfors, P., and D. Makinson, ‘Nonmonotonic Inference Based on Expectations’, Artificial Intelligence 65:197–245, 1994.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. [11]
    Hansson, S. O., ‘Taking Belief Bases Seriously’, in D. Prawitz and D. Westerståhl (eds), Logic and Philosophy in Uppsala, Synthese Library, Vol. 236, Kluwer: 13–28, 1994.Google Scholar
  12. [12]
    Hansson, S. O., ‘Formalization in Philosophy’, Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6(2): 162–75, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. [13]
    Hansson, S. O., and E. J. Olsson, ‘Providing Foundations for Coherentism’, Erkenntnis 51:243–65, 1999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. [14]
    Horwich, P., Probability and Evidence, Cambridge University Press, 1982.Google Scholar
  15. [15]
    Kant, I., Critique of Practical Reason, Vol. 5 of Kant's Gesammelte Schriften, Walter de Gruyter, 1902 [1788].Google Scholar
  16. [16]
    Lehrer, K., Theory of Knowledge, first edition, Routledge, 1990.Google Scholar
  17. [17]
    Lehrer, K., Theory of Knowledge, second revised edition, Westview Press, 2000.Google Scholar
  18. [18]
    Levi, I., The Fixation of Belief and Its Undoing: Changing Beliefs through Inquiry, Cambridge University Press, 1991.Google Scholar
  19. [19]
    Lewis, D., ‘Completeness and Decidability of Three Logics of Counterfactual Conditionals’, Theoria 37:74–85, 1971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. [20]
    Lewis, D., Counterfactuals, Blackwell, 1973.Google Scholar
  21. [21]
    LindstrÖm, S., ‘A Semantic Approach to Nonmonotonic Reasoning: Inference Operations and Choice’, Uppsala Prints and Preprints in Philosophy 6, Department of Philosophy, University of Uppsala, 1991.Google Scholar
  22. [22]
    Makinson, D., ‘General Theory of Cumulative Inference’, in M. Reinfrank et al. (eds), Non-Monotonic Reasoning. Proceedings of the 2ndInternational Workshop 1988, Springer LNAI 346:1–18, 1989.Google Scholar
  23. [23]
    Makinson, D., ‘General Patterns of Nonmonotonic Reasoning’, in D. M. Gabbay et al. (eds), Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming, Vol. 3: Nonmonotonic Reasoning and Uncertain Reasoning, Oxford University Press: 35–110, 1994.Google Scholar
  24. [24]
    Makinson, D., ‘Screened Revision’, in S. O. Hansson (ed.), Non-prioritized Belief Revision, Theoria 63, Part 1–2: 14–23, 1997.Google Scholar
  25. [25]
    Makinson, D., and P. GÄrdenfors, ‘Relations Between the Logic of Theory Change and Nonmonotonic Logic’, in A. Fuhrmann and M. Morreau (eds), The Logic of Theory Change, Springer LNAI 465: 185–205, 1991.Google Scholar
  26. [26]
    Olsson, E. J., ‘A Coherence Interpretation of Semi-revision’, in S. O. Hansson (ed.), Non-prioritized Belief Revision, Theoria 63, Part 1–2: 105–34, 1997.Google Scholar
  27. [27]
    Olsson, E. J., ‘Doxastic Choice and the Unity of Reason’, in R. Sliwinski (ed.), Philosophical Crumbs. Essays dedicated to Ann-Mari Henschen-Dahlquist on the occasion of her seventy-fifth birthday, Department of Philosophy, University of Uppsala: 161–67, 1999.Google Scholar
  28. [28]
    Rauscher, F., ‘Kant's Two Priorities of Practical Reason’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 6(3): 397–419, 1998.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. [29]
    Rott, H., ‘Belief Contraction in the Context of the General Theory of Rational Choice’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 58(4): 1426–50, 1993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. [30]
    Rott, H., ‘Vom Primat der praktischen Vernunft. Logische Regeln als Regeln rationaler Wahl’, in Perspectives in Analytical Philosophy, Vol. 1, G. Meggle (ed.), Walter de Gruyter: 138–47, 1997.Google Scholar
  31. [31]
    Rott, H., Making Up One's Mind: Foundations, Coherence, Nonmonotonicity, German Habilitationsschrift, University of Constance, 1996.Google Scholar
  32. [32]
    Rott, H., Change, Choice and Inference, Oxford Logic Guides No. 42, Oxford University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
  33. [33]
    Segerberg, K., ‘Default Logic as Dynamic Doxastic Logic’, in V. Halbach and E. J. Olsson (eds), Coherence and Dynamics of Belief, Erkenntnis 50(2–3): 333–52, 1999.Google Scholar
  34. [34]
    Sen, A., ‘Internal Consistency of Choice’, Econometrica 61:495–521, 1993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2003

Authors and Affiliations

  • Erik J. Olsson
    • 1
  1. 1.Fachbereich PhilosophieUniversität KonstanzKonstanzGermany

Personalised recommendations