Advertisement

Continental Philosophy Review

, Volume 35, Issue 3, pp 245–279 | Cite as

Dreyfus on expertise: The limits of phenomenological analysis

  • Evan M. Selinger
  • Robert P. Crease
Article

Abstract

Dreyfus's model of expert skill acquisition is philosophically important because it shifts the focus on expertise away from its social and technical externalization in STS, and its relegation to the historical and psychological context of discovery in the classical philosophy of science, to universal structures of embodied cognition and affect. In doing so he explains why experts are not best described as ideologues and why their authority is not exclusively based on social networking. Moreover, by phenomenologically analyzing expertise from a first person perspective, he reveals the limitations of, and sometimes superficial treatment that comes from, investigating expertise from a third person perspective. Thus, he shows that expertise is a prime example of a subject that is essential to science but can only be fully elaborated with the aid of phenomenological tools. However, both Dreyfus's descriptive model and his normative claims are flawed due to the lack of hermeneutical sensitivity. He assumes an expert's knowledge has crystallized out of contextual sensitivity plus experience, and that an expert has shed, during the training process, whatever prejudices, ideologies, hidden agendas, or other forms of cultural embeddedness, that person might have begun with. One would never imagine, from Dreyfus's account, that society could possibly be endangered by experts, only how society's expectations and actions could endanger experts. The stories of actual controversies not only shows things do not work the way Dreyfus claims, but also that it would be less salutary if they did. Such stories amount to counterexamples to Dreyfus's normative claims, and point to serious shortcomings in his arguments.

Keywords

Social Networking Training Process Political Philosophy Skill Acquisition Phenomenological Analysis 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  1. Barbour, I. (1993). Ethics in an Age of Technology. San Francisco: Harper Collins.Google Scholar
  2. Black, B., Ayala, F. and Saffran-Brinks, C. (1994). “Science and the Law in the Wake of Daubert.” Texas Law Review 72: 715–802.Google Scholar
  3. Brewer, S. (1998). Scientific Expert Testimony and Intellectual Due Process. The Yale Law Review 107(4): 1535–1681.Google Scholar
  4. Callon, M. (2001). Researchers in the Wild and the Rise of Technical Democracy. Paper presented at Knowledge in Plural Contexts, Science and Technology Studies, Université de Lausanne, Switzerland.Google Scholar
  5. Caudill, D. and Redding, R. (2000). Junk Philosophy of Science? The Paradox of Expertise and Interdisciplinarity in Federal Courts. Washington and Lee Law Review 57(3): 685–766.Google Scholar
  6. Collins, H. M. (1995). Humans, Machines, and the Structure of Knowledge. Stanford Humanities Review 4(2): 67–83.Google Scholar
  7. Collins, H. (2001). Tacit Knowledge, Trust, and the Q of Sapphire. Social Studies of Science 31: 71–86.Google Scholar
  8. Crease, R. P. (1997). Hermeneutics and the Natural Sciences: Introduction. In R. Crease (Ed.), Hermeneutics and the Natural Sciences. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 1–12.Google Scholar
  9. Crease, R. P. (1999). Conflicting Interpretations of Risk: the Case of Brookhaven's Spent Fuel Rods. Technology, 6: 495–500.Google Scholar
  10. Crease, R. P. (2001). Anxious History: The High Flux Beam Reactor and Brookhaven National Laboratory. Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences 32(1): 41–56.Google Scholar
  11. Crease, R. P. (2002a). Compromising Peer Review. Physics World, January 2002, 17.Google Scholar
  12. Crease, R. P. (2002b). The Pleasure of Popular Dance. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39:2, 2002, 106–120.Google Scholar
  13. Crease, R. P. (2002c). Fallout: Issues in the Study, Treatment, and Reparations of Exposed Marshall Islanders. In R. Figueroa and S. Harding (Eds.), Exploring Diversity in the Philosophy of Science and Technology, Routledge (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  14. Dreyfus, H. (1967). Alchemy and Artificial Intelligence. Rand, Paper P3244.Google Scholar
  15. Dreyfus, H. and Dreyfus, S. (1985). From Socrates to Expert Systems: The Limits of Calculative Rationality. In C. Mitcham and A. Huning (Eds.), Philosophy and Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 111–130.Google Scholar
  16. Dreyfus, H. and Dreyfus, S. (1986). Mind Over Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  17. Dreyfus, H. and Dreyfus, S. (1990). What is Morality? A Phenomenological Account of the Development of Ethical Expertise. In D. Rasmussen (Ed.), Universalism vs. Communitarianism: Contemporary Debates in Ethics. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 237–264.Google Scholar
  18. Dreyfus, H. (1991). Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Dreyfus, H. (1992). What Computers Still Can't Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Dreyfus, H., Spinosa, C., and Flores, F. (1997). Disclosing Worlds: Entrepreneurship, Democratic Action, and the Cultivation of Solidarity. Cambridge, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  21. Dreyfus, H. (1998). Intelligence Without Representation. Network for Non-Scholastic Working Paper, Department of Philosophy, Aarhus University, Denmark.Google Scholar
  22. Dreyfus, H. (1999a). How Neuroscience Supports Merleau-Ponty's Account of Learning. Paper presented at the Network for Non-Scholastic Learning Conference, Sonderborg, Denmark.Google Scholar
  23. Dreyfus, H. (1999b). The Primacy of Phenomenology over Logical Analysis. Philosophical Topics 27(2): 3–24.Google Scholar
  24. Dreyfus, H. (2000). Could Anything be More Intelligible than Everyday Intelligibility? Reinterpreting Division I of Being and Time in the Light of Division II. In J. Faulconer and M. Wrathall (Eds.), Appropriating Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 155–170.Google Scholar
  25. Dreyfus, H. (2001). On the Internet. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  26. Feyerabend, P. (1987). Science in a Free Society. London: Verso.Google Scholar
  27. Feenberg, A. and Hannay, A. (Eds.) (1995). Technology and the Politics of Knowledge. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Huber, P. (1991). Galileo's Revenge: Junk Science in the Courtroom. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  29. Huber, P. and Foster, K. (1999). Judging Science: Scientific Knowledge and the Federal Courts. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Husserl, E. (1973) Cartesian Meditations and the Paris Lectures, ed. S. Strasser. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  31. Ibsen, H. (1988). Ibsen: The Complete Major Prose Plays, trans. R. Fjelde. New York: New American Library.Google Scholar
  32. Ihde, D. (1998). Expanding Hermeneutics: Visualism in Science. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Jasanoff, S.(1995). Science at the Bar: Law, Science, and Technology in America. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Latour, B. (1999). Pandora's Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  35. MacKenzie, D. (1996). Knowing Machines: Essays on Technological Change. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  36. Mialet, H. (1999). Do Angels Have Bodies? Two Stories about Subjectivity in Science: The Cases of William X and Mister H. Social Studies of Science 29(4): 551–582.Google Scholar
  37. Pappas, G. (1994). Experts. Acta Analytica 9(12).Google Scholar
  38. Polanyi, M. (1974). Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  39. Rawls, J. (1968). Two Concepts of Rules. In J. Thomson and G. Dworkin (Eds.), Ethics. New York: Harper & Row, pp. 104–135.Google Scholar
  40. Reber, A. (1995). Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge: An Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Rouse, J. (1987). Knowledge and Power: Toward a Political Philosophy of Science. New York: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Ryle, G. (1984). The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  43. Schon, D. (1983). The Reflective Practitioner. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  44. Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Searle, J. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  46. Selinger, E. The Paradox of Expertise. PhD Dissertation, Stony Brook University (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  47. Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999). The Primacy of Movement. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  48. Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2000). Kinetic Tactile-Kinesthetic Bodies: Ontogenetical Foundations of Apprenticeship Learning. Human Studies 23: 343–370.Google Scholar
  49. Stengers, I. (2000). The Invention of Modern Science, trans. D. Smith. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  50. Turner, S. (2001) What is the Problem With Experts? Social Studies of Science 31: 123–149.Google Scholar
  51. Young, I. (1998). Throwing like a Girl. In D. Welton (Ed.), Body and Flesh: A Philosophical Reader. Oxford and Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 259–273.Google Scholar
  52. Walton, D. (1997). Appeal to Expert Opinion: Arguments from Authority. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Williams, R. (1976). Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Winner, L. (1995). Citizen Virtues in a Technological Order. In A. Feenberg and A. Hannay (Eds.), Technology and the Politics of Knowledge. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 65–84.Google Scholar
  55. Winograd, T. (1995). Heidegger and the Design of Computer Systems. In A. Feenberg and A. Hannay (Eds.), Technology and the Politics of Knowledge. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 108–127.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2002

Authors and Affiliations

  • Evan M. Selinger
    • 1
  • Robert P. Crease
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyStony Brook UniversityStony BrookUSA

Personalised recommendations