Social Justice Research

, Volume 15, Issue 2, pp 165–184 | Cite as

The Preference for Indirect Harm

  • Edward B. Royzman
  • Jonathan Baron

Abstract

We presented subjects pairs of hypothetical scenarios. The action in each scenario harmed some people in order to aid others. In one member of the pair, the harm was a direct result of the action. In the other member, it was an indirect byproduct. Subjects preferred the indirect harm to the direct harm. This result could not be fully explained in terms of differences in judgments about which option was more active, more intentional, more likely to cause harm, or more subject to the disapproval of others. Taken together, these findings provide evidence for a new bias in judgment, a tendency to favor indirectly harmful options over directly harmful alternatives, irrespective of the associated outcomes, intentions, or self-presentational concerns. We speculate that this bias could originate from the use of a typical but somewhat unreliable property of harmful acts, their directness, as a cue to moral evaluation. We discuss the implications of the bias for a range of social issues, including the distinction between passive and active euthanasia, legal deterrence, and the rhetoric of affirmative action.

tragic moral choices omission bias direct vs. indirect harm Kant 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Aquinas, T. (1947). Summa Theologica (translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province), Benziger Brothers. Retrieved from http://www.newadvent.org/summa/Google Scholar
  2. Baron, J. (1994). Nonconsequentialist decisions (with commentary and reply). Behav. Brain Sci. 17: 142.Google Scholar
  3. Baron, J. (1995). Blind justice: Fairness to groups and the donoharm principle. J. Behav. Decis. Making 8: 7183.Google Scholar
  4. Baron, J. (1998). Judgment Misguided: Intuition and Error in Public Decision Making, Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  5. Baron, J., and Ritov, I. (1994). Reference points and omission bias. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 59: 475-498.Google Scholar
  6. Bennett, J. (1966). Whatever the consequences. Analysis 26: 83-102.Google Scholar
  7. Birnbaum, M. H. (1999). Testing critical properties of decision making on the Internet. Psychol. Sci. 10: 399-407.Google Scholar
  8. Birnbaum, M. H. (ed.) (2000). Psychological Experiments on the Internet, Academic Press, New York.Google Scholar
  9. Davis, N. A. (1995). The priority of avoiding harm. In Steinbock, B., and Norcross, A. (eds.), Killing and Letting Die, 2nd edn., Fordham University Press, New York, pp. 301-302.Google Scholar
  10. Hsee, C. K., Loewenstein, G. F., Blount, S., and Bazerman, M. H. (1999). Preference reversals between joint and separate evaluations of options: A review and theoretical analysis. Psychol. Bull. 125: 576-590.Google Scholar
  11. Jervis, R. (1976). Perception and Misperception in International Politics, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
  12. Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., and Thaler, R. H. (1990). Experimental tests of the endowment effect and the Coase theorem. J. Pol. Econ. 98: 1325-1348.Google Scholar
  13. Kant, I. (1983). Grounding for the metaphysics of morals. In Kant, I. (ed.), Ethical Philosophy (Ellington, trans.), J. W., Hackett, Indianapolis, IN. (Originally published 1785)Google Scholar
  14. Kuhse, H. (1987). The Sanctity of Life Doctrine in Medicine: A Critique, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.Google Scholar
  15. Lorenz, K. (1963). On aggression (M. K. Wilson, trans.). Harcourt, Brace & World, New York.Google Scholar
  16. McGraw, K. O., Tew, M. D., and Williams, J. E. (2000). The integrity of Web-delivered experiments: Can you trust the data? Psychol. Sci. 11: 502-506.Google Scholar
  17. Meszaros, J. R., Asch, D. A., Baron, J., Hershey, J. C., Kunreuther, H., & Schwartz-Buzaglo, J. (1996). Cognitive processes and the decisions of some parents to forego pertussis vaccination for their children. J. Clin. Epidem. 49: 697-703.Google Scholar
  18. Midgley, M. (1995). Beast and man: The roots of human nature. Routledge, New York.Google Scholar
  19. Milgram, S. (1974). Obedience to Authority, Harper and Row, New York.Google Scholar
  20. Petrinovich, L., and O'Neill, P. (1996). Influence of wording and framing effects on moral intuitions. Ethnol. Sociobiol. 17: 145-171.Google Scholar
  21. Quinn, W. (1989). Actions, intentions, and consequences: The doctrine of double effect. Philos. Public Aff. 18: 334-351.Google Scholar
  22. Rachels, J. (1986). The Elements of Moral Philosophy, McGraw Hill, New York.Google Scholar
  23. Ritov, I., and Baron, J. (1990). Reluctance to vaccinate: Omission bias and ambiguity. J. Beh. Decis. Making 3: 263-277.Google Scholar
  24. Samuelson, W., and Zeckhauser, R. (1988). Statusquo bias in decision making. J. Risk Uncert. 1: 759.Google Scholar
  25. Spranca, M., Minsk, E., and Baron, J. (1991). Omission and commission in judgment and choice. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 27: 76-105.Google Scholar
  26. Steinbock, B. (1995). Introduction. In Steinbock, B., and Norcross, A. (eds.), Killing and Letting Die, 2nd edn. Fordham University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  27. Trammell, R. (1995). Saving life and taking life. In Steinbock, B., and Norcross, A. (eds.), Killing and Letting Die, 2nd edn., Fordham University Press, New York, pp. 290-298.Google Scholar
  28. Zeelenberg, M., Beattie, J., van der Plight, J., and de Vries, N. K. (1996). Consequences of regret aversion: Effects of expected feedback on risky decision making. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 65: 148-158.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Plenum Publishing Corporation 2002

Authors and Affiliations

  • Edward B. Royzman
    • 1
  • Jonathan Baron
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PsychologyUniversity of PennsylvaniaPhiladelphia

Personalised recommendations