Philosophical Studies

, Volume 97, Issue 3, pp 293–316 | Cite as

Rigidity and Kind

  • Joseph LaPorte
Article

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Aune, Bruce (1994): 'Determinate Meaning and Analytic Truth', in G. Debrock and M. Hulswit (eds.), Living Doubt, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 55-65.Google Scholar
  2. Boër, Steven (1985): 'Substance and Kind: Reflections on the New Theory of Reference', in B. K. Matilal and J. L. Shaw (eds.), Analytical Philosophy in Comparative Perspective, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 103-150.Google Scholar
  3. Bolton, C. J. (1996): 'Proper Names, Taxonomic Names and Necessity', The Philosophical Quarterly 46, 145-157.Google Scholar
  4. Boyd, Richard (1992): 'Constructivism, Realism, and Philosophical Method', in John Earman (ed.), Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations, Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 131-198.Google Scholar
  5. Burge, Tyler (1982): 'Other Bodies', in A Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 97-120.Google Scholar
  6. Cook, Monte (1980): 'If “Cat” is a Rigid Designator, What Does it Designate?', Philosophical Studies 37, 61-64.Google Scholar
  7. Darwin, Charles (ed.) (1888): The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, ed. Francis Darwin, 2 vols. New York: D. Appleton and Co.Google Scholar
  8. De Sousa, Ronald (1984): 'The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds', Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14, 561-580.Google Scholar
  9. De Queiroz, Kevin and Michael J. Donoghue (1988): 'Phylogenetic Systematics and the Species Problem', Cladistics 4, 317-338.Google Scholar
  10. Devitt, Michael (1996): Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Devitt, Michael and Sterelny Kim (1987): Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Donnellan, Keith (1983): 'Kripke and Putnam on Natural Kind Terms', in Carl Ginet and Sydney Shoemaker (eds.), Knowledge and Mind, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 84-104.Google Scholar
  13. Douven, Igor and J. van Brakel (forthcoming): 'Can the World Help Us in Fixing the Unique Reference of Natural Kind Terms?', Journal for General Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
  14. Ereshefsky, Marc (ed.) (1992): The Units of Evolution: Essays on the Nature of Species, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  15. Ghiselin, Michael (1987): 'Species Concepts, Individuality, and Objectivity', Biology and Philosophy 2, 127-143.Google Scholar
  16. Kripke, Saul (1980): Naming and Necessity, Cambridge,MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Kuhn, Thomas (1990): 'Dubbing and Redubbing: The Vulnerability of Rigid Designation', in C. Wade Savage (ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14: Scientific Theories, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 208-318.Google Scholar
  18. LaPorte, J. (1996): 'Chemical Kind Term Reference and the Discovery of Essence', Noûs 30, 112-132.Google Scholar
  19. LaPorte, J. (1997): 'Essential Membership', Philosophy of Science 64, 96-112.Google Scholar
  20. Leplin, Jarrett (1988): 'Is Essentialism Unscientific?', Philosophy of Science 55, 493-510.Google Scholar
  21. Locke, John (1975): An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  22. Macbeth, Danielle (1995): 'Names, Natural Kind Terms, and Rigid Designation', Philosophical Studies 79, 259-281.Google Scholar
  23. Mondadori, Fabrizio (1978): 'Interpreting Modal Semantics', in F. Guenther and C. Rohrer (eds.), Studies in Formal Semantics, Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Co., pp. 13-40.Google Scholar
  24. Nersessian, Nancy (1984): Faraday to Einstein: Constructing Meaning in Scientific Theories, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  25. Putnam, Hilary (1975): 'The Meaning of “Meaning”', in Mind, Language and Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215-271.Google Scholar
  26. Putnam, Hilary (1977): 'Is Semantics Possible?', in Steven P. Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity, and Natural Kinds, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 102-118.Google Scholar
  27. Putnam, Hilary (1983): Realism and Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Salmon, Nathan (1980): Reference and Essence, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Schwartz, Steven P. (1977): 'Introduction', in his Naming, Necessity, and Natural Kinds, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 13-41.Google Scholar
  30. Schwartz, Steven P. (1978): 'Putnam on Artifacts', The Philosophical Review 87, 566-574.Google Scholar
  31. Schwartz, Steven P. (1980): 'Formal Semantics and Natural Kind Terms', Philosophical Studies 38, 189-198.Google Scholar
  32. Shapere, Dudley (1982): 'Reason, Reference, and the Quest for Knowledge', Philosophy of Science 49, 1-24.Google Scholar
  33. Sidelle, Alan (1989): Necessity, Essence, and Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Sidelle, Alan (1992): 'Rigidity, Ontology, and Semantic Structure', The Journal of Philosophy 89, 410-430.Google Scholar
  35. Sidelle, Alan (1995): 'A Semantic Account of Rigidity', Philosophical Studies 80, 69-105.Google Scholar
  36. Steward, Helen (1990): 'Identity Statements and the Necessary A Posteriori', The Journal of Philosophy 87, 385-398.Google Scholar
  37. Van Brakel, J. (1992): 'Natural Kinds and Manifest Forms of Life', Dialectica 46, 243-261.Google Scholar
  38. Van Valen, L. (1989): 'Metascience', Evolutionary Theory 9, 99-103.Google Scholar
  39. Wiggins, David (1994): 'Putnam's Doctrine of Natural Kind Words and Frege's Doctrines of Sense, Reference, and Extension: Can They Cohere?', in Peter Clark and Bob Hale (eds.), Reading Putnam, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 13-41.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2000

Authors and Affiliations

  • Joseph LaPorte

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations