Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics

, Volume 15, Issue 3, pp 289–303 | Cite as

The Food Debate: Ethical versus Substantial Equivalence

  • Sylvie Pouteau
Article

Abstract

Substantial equivalence (SE) has beenintroduced to assess novel foods, includinggenetically modified (GM) food, by means ofcomparison with traditional food. Besides anumber of objections concerning its scientificvalidity for risk assessment, the maindifficulty with SE is that it implies that foodcan be qualified on a purely substantial basis.SE embodies the assumption that only reductivescientific arguments are legitimate fordecision-making in public policy due to theemphasis on legal issues. However, the surge ofthe food debate clearly shows that thistechnocratic model is not accepted anymore.Food is more than physico-chemical substanceand encompasses values such as quality andethics. These values are legitimate in theirown right and require that new democraticprocesses are set up for transverse,transdisciplinary assessment in partnershipwith society. The notion of equivalence canprovide a reference scale in which to examinethe various legitimate factors involved:substance (SE), quality (QualitativeEquivalence: QE), and ethics (EthicalEquivalence: EE). QE requires that newqualitative methods of evaluation that are notbased on reductive principles are developed. EEcan provide a basis for the development of anEthical Assurance as a counterpart of QualityAssurance in the food sector. In France, asecond circle of expertise is being set up toaddress the social issues in food public policybeside classical risk assessment by the firstcircle of expertise. Since ethics is likely tobecome an organizing principle of the secondcircle, the equivalence ethical framework canprove instrumental in this context.

equivalence ethical framework,/kwd>  ``Ethical Assurance'' second circle of expertise food integrity genetically modified (GM) food legitimate factors quality substantial equivalence 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Aristotle, Magna Moralia, in G. C. Armstrong (ed.) (Loeb Classical Library, Cambridge MA and London, 1935).Google Scholar
  2. Bortoft, H., “Counterfeit and Authentic Wholes: Finding a Mean for Dwelling in Nature,” in D. Seamon and A. Zajon (eds.), Goethe'sWay of Science - A phenomenology of Nature (New York, 1998), pp. 278–298.Google Scholar
  3. Brown, J. K. M., “How to Feed theWorld, in Two Contradictory Lessons,” Trends in Plant Sciences 3 (1998), 409–410.Google Scholar
  4. Callon, M., “Des Différentes Formes de Démocratie Technique,” Annales des Mines (1998), 63–73.Google Scholar
  5. Clark, E. A. and H. Lehman, “Assessment of GM Crops in Commercial Agriculture,” Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 14 (2001), 3–28.Google Scholar
  6. CNA, L'Étiquetage des Nouveaux Aliments et des Nouveaux Ingrédients Constitués d'Organismes Génétiquement Modifiés ou Issus d'Organismes Génétiquement Modifiés, Notice n°17, http://www.agriculture.gouv.fr/alim/part/cna.html (1997).Google Scholar
  7. CNA, Concertation et Débat Public en Matière de Politique Alimentaire: Enjeux et Aspects Méthodologiques, Notice n°29, http://www.agriculture.gouv.fr/alim/part/cna.html (2001a).Google Scholar
  8. CNA, Rapport et Avis Relatif à l'Étiquetage des Aliments et Ingrédients Constitués d'Organismes Génétiquement Modifiés ou Issus d'Organismes Génétiquement Modifiés, Notice n°31, http://www.agriculture.gouv.fr/alim/part/cna.html (2001b).Google Scholar
  9. Daily, G. C., and B. H. Walker, “Seeking the Great Transition,” Nature 403 (2000), 243-245.Google Scholar
  10. Descartes, R., Discourse on Method and The Meditations (Penguin Classics, London 1987).Google Scholar
  11. Doubleday, R., “Knowledge and the Governance of Biotechnology,” Politeia 62 (2001), 22–33.Google Scholar
  12. FAO, Biotechnology and Food Safety, Report, Rome, http://www.fao.org/ (1996).Google Scholar
  13. FAO, Ethical issues in Food and Agriculture, Report, http://www.fao.org/ethics/ser_en.htm (2001).Google Scholar
  14. Fears, R. and E. Tambuyzer, “Core Ethical Values for European Bioindustries,” Nature Biotechnology 17 (1999), 114–115.Google Scholar
  15. Guerinot, M. L., “The Green Revolution Strikes Gold,” Science 287 (2000), 241 and 243.Google Scholar
  16. Habermas, J., The Theory of Communicative Action (Beacon Press, Boston, 1985).Google Scholar
  17. Ho, M.-W. and R. A. Steinbrecher, “Fatal Flaws in Food Safety Assessment: Critique of the Joint FAO/WHO Biotechnology and Food Safety Report,” Physicians and Scientists for Responsible Application of Science and Technology (PSRAST) homepage, http://www.psrast.org/ (1998).Google Scholar
  18. Husset, M.-J., in L'Opinion Publique Face aux Plantes Transgéniques (Albin Michel, Paris, 1998), pp. 110–117.Google Scholar
  19. Jasanoff, S., “Ordering Life: Law and the Normalisation of Biotechnology,” Politeia 62 (2001), 22–33.Google Scholar
  20. Kinderlerer, J., “Is a European Convention on the Ethical Use of Modern Biotechnology Needed?” Trends in Biotechnology 18 (2000), 87–90.Google Scholar
  21. Koechlin, F., “Solutions of Agronomic Problems Based on 'Ecological Integrity',” in D. Heaf and J. Wirz (eds.), Intrinsic Value and Integrity of Plants in the Context of Genetic Engineering (Ifgene, UK: http://www.anth.org/Ifgene/papersMay2001.htm, 2001), pp. 39–40.Google Scholar
  22. Ladrière, J., L'Éthique dans l'Uunivers de la Rationalité (Artel-Fides, Namur, 1997).Google Scholar
  23. Mann, C. C., “Crop Scientists Seek a New Revolution,” Science 283 (1999), 310–314.Google Scholar
  24. Mepham, B., “'Würde der Kreatur' and the Common Morality,” Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 13 (2000), 65–78.Google Scholar
  25. Millstone, E., E. Brunner, and S. Mayer, “Beyond 'Substantial Equivalence',” Nature 401 (1999), 525–526.Google Scholar
  26. OECD, Safety Evaluation of Foods Derived by Modern Biotechnology - Concepts and Principles. Report, Paris (1993).Google Scholar
  27. OECD, OECD Workshop on the Toxicological and Nutritional Testing of Novel Foods. Report, Aussois (1998).Google Scholar
  28. Pouteau, S., “Beyond Substantial Equivalence: Ethical Equivalence,” Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 13 (2000), 273–291.Google Scholar
  29. Sagar, A., A. Daemmrich, and M. Ashiya, “The Tragedy of the Commoners: Biotechnology and its Publics,” Nature Biotechnology 18 (2000), 2–4.Google Scholar
  30. Schmidt, H., “Dignity of Man and Intrinsic Value of the Creature (Würde der Kreatur) Conflicting or Interdependent Legal Concepts in Legal Reality?” in D. Heaf and J. Wirz (eds.), Intrinsic Value and Integrity of Plants in the Context of Genetic Engineering (Ifgene, UK: http://www.anth.org/Ifgene/papersMay2001.htm, 2001), pp. 19–23.Google Scholar
  31. Tilman, D., “The Greening of the Green Revolution,” Nature 396 (1998), 211–212.Google Scholar
  32. Verhoog, H., “Genetic Modification of Animals: Should Science and Ethics be Integrated?” The Monist 79 (1996), 247–263.Google Scholar
  33. Viney, G. and P. Kourilsky, Le Principe de précaution. Report, http://www.finances.gouv. fr/ogm/index-bas.htm#textes (1999).Google Scholar
  34. Ye, X., S. Al-Babili, A. Klöti, J. Zhang, P. Lucca, P. Beyer, and I. Potrykus, “Engineering the Provitamin A (Beta-Carotene) Biosynthetic Pathway into (Carotenoid-Free) Rice Endosperm,” Science 287 (2000), 303–305. SYLVIE POUTEAU Laboratoire de Biologie Cellulaire, INRA Route de Saint-Cyr, F78026 Versailles cedex, France Ethos INRA (http://www.inra.fr/Internet/Directions/SED/EES/) E-mail: Sylvie.Pouteau@versailles.inra.fr Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2002

Authors and Affiliations

  • Sylvie Pouteau
    • 1
  1. 1.Laboratoire de Biologie Cellulaire, INRA, Route de Saint-CyrEthos INRA (Versailles cedexFrance

Personalised recommendations