Minds and Machines

, Volume 10, Issue 1, pp 31–52 | Cite as

Reverse Psychologism, Cognition and Content

  • Terry Dartnall
Article
  • 65 Downloads

Abstract

The confusion between cognitive states and the content of cognitive states that gives rise to psychologism also gives rise to reverse psychologism. Weak reverse psychologism says that we can study cognitive states by studying content – for instance, that we can study the mind by studying linguistics or logic. This attitude is endemic in cognitive science and linguistic theory. Strong reverse psychologism says that we can generate cognitive states by giving computers representations that express the content of cognitive states and that play a role in causing appropriate behaviour. This gives us strong representational, classical AI (REPSCAI), and I argue that it cannot succeed. This is not, as Searle claims in his Chinese Room Argument, because syntactic manipulation cannot generate content. Syntactic manipulation can generate content, and this is abundantly clear in the Chinese Room scenano. REPSCAI cannot succeed because inner content is not sufficient for cognition, even when the representations that carry the content play a role in generating appropriate behaviour.

cognition content psychologism reverse psychologism meaning proposition cognitive science strong AI Chinese Room Chinese Gymnasium 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Amble, T. (1987), Logic Programming and Knowledge Engineering, Wokingham: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
  2. Barr, A. and Feigenbaum, E. A. (1981), The Handbook of Artificial Intelligence, vol. I, Reading Mass: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
  3. Bickhard, M. (1998), ‘Genuine Representations in Artificial Systems’, in G. Antoniou and J. Slaney (eds.), Advanced Topics in Artificial Intelligence, 11th Australian Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Selected Papers. Springer: Berlin.Google Scholar
  4. Bickhard, M. and Terveen, L. (1995), Foundational Issues in Artificial Intelligence and Cognitive Science-Impasse and Solution. Amsterdam: Elsevier Scientific.Google Scholar
  5. Bresnan, J. (1982), The Mental Representation of Grammatical Relations, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Brooks, R. (1991), ‘Intelligence without Representation’, Artificial Intelligence, 47, pp. 139-159.Google Scholar
  7. Burge, T. (1979). ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, iv.Google Scholar
  8. Chomsky, N. (1965), Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Chomsky, N. (1968), Language and Mind, New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. Extended edition, 1972.Google Scholar
  10. Churchland, P. M. and Churchland, P. S. (1990), ‘Could a Machine Think?’, Scientific American, 262: 1, pp. 26-31.Google Scholar
  11. Cussins, A. (1990), ‘The Connectionist Construction of Concepts’, in M. Boden (ed), The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 368-440.Google Scholar
  12. Dennett, D. (1981), ‘Three Kinds of Intentional Psychology’, in R. Healy (ed), Reduction, Time and Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in D. Dennett, 1987b, pp. 43-68.Google Scholar
  13. Dennett, D. (1987a), ‘Fast Thinking’, in D. Dennett, 1987b, pp. 324-337.Google Scholar
  14. Dennett, D. (1987b), The Intentional Stance, Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  15. Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought, New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.Google Scholar
  16. Fodor, J. (1980), ‘Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3.Google Scholar
  17. Ford, M. (1988), ‘Parsing Complexity and a Theory of Parsing’, in G. Carlson and M. Tanenhaus (eds.), Linguistic Structure in Language Processing, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  18. Frege, G. (1967), The Basic Laws of Arithmetic, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  19. Haugeland, J. (1985), Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea, Cambridge, Mass: MIT/Bradford.Google Scholar
  20. Heil, J. (1993), The Nature of True Minds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Hinton, G. (1985), ‘Learning in Parallel Networks’, Byte, April, pp. 265-273.Google Scholar
  22. Hinton, G. (1986), ‘Learning Distributed Representations of Concepts’, Proceedings of the Eighth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, Amherst, MA. pp. 1-12.Google Scholar
  23. Husserl, E. (1891), Philosophie der Arithmetik, Leipzig: C.E.M. Pfeffer.Google Scholar
  24. Husserl, E. (1962), Ideas-General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  25. Husserl, E. (1970), Logical Investigations, 1, New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
  26. Katz, J. (1981), Language and Other Abstract Objects, New Jersey: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  27. Lemmon, E. (1966), ‘Sentences, Statements and Propositions’, in B. Williams and A. Montefiore (eds), British Analytical Philosophy, London: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  28. Locke, J. (1690), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. My edition is edited by A.D. Woozley, London: Fontana, 1964.Google Scholar
  29. Lotze, R (1874), Logik, Leipzig. Translated by Helen Dendy as Logic, Oxford, 1884.Google Scholar
  30. Macnamara, J. (1986), A Border Dispute: The Place of Logic in Psychology, Cambridge MA: MIT Bradford.Google Scholar
  31. Mill, J. (1843) A System of Logic. London: Longmans, Green, Reader & Dyer.Google Scholar
  32. Mill, J. (1865), Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, Boston: William V. Spencer.Google Scholar
  33. Putnam, H. (1975), ‘TheMeaning of “Meaning”’, in K. Gunderson (ed), Language, Mind and Knowledge, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in H. Putnam (1975), Mind, Language and Reality-Philosophical Papers, vol. 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Rich, E. (1983), Artificial Intelligence, Auckland: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  35. Ryle, G. (1949), The Concept of Mind, Hutchinson. Reprinted Harmondsworth: Penguin (1963).Google Scholar
  36. Schank, R. C. and Abelson, R. P. (1977), Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding, Hillsdale: Laurence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  37. Searle, J. (1980), ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, pp. 417-427.Google Scholar
  38. Searle, J. (1990), ‘Is the Brain's Mind a Computer Program?’, Scientific American, 262: 1, pp. 20-31.Google Scholar
  39. Searle, J. (1995), ‘Mind, syntax, and semantics’, in T. Honderlich (ed), The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 580-581.Google Scholar
  40. Sejnowski, T. and Rosenberg, C. (1986), ‘NETtalk: a Parallel Network that Learns to Read Aloud’, John Hopkins Electrical Engineering and Computer Science Technical Report, JHU/EEC-86/01. Google Scholar
  41. Shanon, B. (1993) The Representational and the Presentational. An Essay in Cognition and the Study of Mind, London: Harvester.Google Scholar
  42. Smith, B. C. (1985), ‘Prologue to Reflection and Semantics in a Procedural Language’, in R. Brachman and H. Levesque (eds), Readings in Knowledge Representation, Los Altos: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
  43. Smith, B. C. (1991), ‘The Owl and the Electric Encyclopedia’, Artificial Intelligence, 47, pp. 251-288.Google Scholar
  44. Smolensky, P. (1988). ‘On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11, pp. 1-74.Google Scholar
  45. Thagard, P. (1996), Mind: Introduction to Cognitive Science, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT/Bradford.Google Scholar
  46. Torrance, S. (1997), ‘A Change of Mind in Cognitive Science’, Metascience, New Series Issue 11.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 2000

Authors and Affiliations

  • Terry Dartnall

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations