Journal of Risk and Uncertainty

, Volume 14, Issue 3, pp 235–257 | Cite as

Explaining the Identifiable Victim Effect

  • KAREN JENNI
  • GEORGE LOEWENSTEIN

Abstract

It is widely believed that people are willing to expend greater resources to save the lives of identified victims than to save equal numbers of unidentified or statistical victims. There are many possible causes of this disparity which have not been enumerated previously or tested empirically. We discuss four possible causes of the identifiable victim effect and present the results of two studies which indicate that the most important cause of the disparity in treatment of identifiable and statistical lives is that, for identifiable victims, a high proportion of those at risk can be saved.

value of life identifiable victims 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Batson, C. Daniel, et al. (1991). “Empathic joy and the empathy-altruism hypothesis.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 62, 413–26.Google Scholar
  2. Bullard, Robert D. (1993). Confronting Environmental Racism: Voices from the Grassroots. Boston: South End Press.Google Scholar
  3. Calabresi, Guido, and Philip Bobbitt (1978). Tragic Choices. New York: W.W. Norton and Co.Google Scholar
  4. Cialdini, Robert B., et al. (1987). “Empathy-based helping: is it selflessly or selfishly motivated?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52, 749–58.Google Scholar
  5. Cohen, M, J. Y. Jaffray, and T. Said (1987). “Experimental comparison of individual behavior under risk and under uncertainty for gains and for losses,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 39, 1–22.Google Scholar
  6. Cushman, John H. Jr. (1994). “Clinton to Order Effort to Make Pollution Fairer,” The NewYork Times, February 10, page A1.Google Scholar
  7. Douglas, Mary (1992). Risk and Blame: Essays in Cultural Theory. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  8. Egan, Timothy (1994). “A 3-Strike Law Shows It's Not as Simple as it Seems,” The New York Times, February 15, p. A1.Google Scholar
  9. Gibbard, Allan (1986). “Risk and Value,” in Douglas MacLean (Ed.), Values at Risk. New Jersey: Rowan and Allanheld.Google Scholar
  10. Gillette, Clayton P., and Thomas D. Hopkins (1988). Federal Agency Valuations of Human Life. Administrative Conference of the United States, Report for Recommendation 88–7.Google Scholar
  11. Glover, Jonathan (1977). Causing Death and Saving Lives. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  12. Goodman, Walter (1993). “TV, by its very nature, can stack the deck,” The New York Times, September 13, p. C20.Google Scholar
  13. Gore, Al (1992). Earth in the Balance: Ecology and the Human Spirit. New York: Plume.Google Scholar
  14. Horowitz, John K. and Richard T. Carson (1993). “Baseline risk and Preference for Reductions in Risk to Life.” Risk Analysis 13 (2), 457–462.Google Scholar
  15. Keeney, Ralph L. (1995). “Understanding Life-Threatening Risks,” Risk Analysis 15 (6).Google Scholar
  16. Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk.” Econometrica 47(2).Google Scholar
  17. Latané, Bibb, and John M. Darley (1970). The Unresponsive Bystander: Why doesn't he help?. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
  18. Linden, Eugene (1988). “Helping Out Putu, Siku and Kanik,” Time Magazine, pp. 76–77. October 31.Google Scholar
  19. MacLean, Douglas (1986). “Social Values and the Distribution of Risk,” in Douglas MacLean (Ed.), Values at Risk. New Jersey: Rowan and Allanheld.Google Scholar
  20. National Research Council (1989). Improving Risk Communication. Washington DC: National Academy Press.Google Scholar
  21. Nisbett, Richard and Lee Ross (1980). Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.Google Scholar
  22. People Weekly (1987). “America's heart goes out to Baby Jessica.” Volume 28:18. November 2.Google Scholar
  23. People Weekly (1990). Volume 33:15. April 16.Google Scholar
  24. Piliavin, Jane A., et al. (1981). Emergency Intervention. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  25. Piliavin, Irving M., Judith Rodin, and Jane A. Piliavin (1969). “Good samaritanism: an underground phenomenon?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 13, 289–299.Google Scholar
  26. Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Massachussetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Rawls, John (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Raynor, Steve (1992). “Cultural Theory and Risk Analysis,” In Seldon Krimsky and Dominic Golding (Eds.), Social Theories of Risk. Connecticut: Praeger Press.Google Scholar
  29. Redelmeier, Donald A. and Amos Tversky (1990). “Occasional Note: Discrepancy Between Medical Decisions for Individual Patients and for Groups,” The New England Journal of Medicine, April 19.Google Scholar
  30. Ritov, Ilana, and Jonathan Baron (1990). “Reluctance to Vaccinate: Omission Bias and Ambiguity,” Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 3, 263–277.Google Scholar
  31. Schelling, T. C. (1968). “The Life You Save May Be Your Own,” in Samuel Chase (Ed.), Problems in Public Expenditure Analysis. Washington DC: The Brookings Institute.Google Scholar
  32. Shotland, R. Lance (1983). “What's wrong with helping behavior research? Only the independent and dependent variables.” Academic Psychology Bulletin 5, 339–350.Google Scholar
  33. Shrader-Frechette, K. S. (1991). Risk and Rationality: Philosophical Foundations for Populist Reforms. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  34. Skelton, George (1993). “A Father's Crusade Born From Pain,” The Los Angeles Times, December 9, p. A3.Google Scholar
  35. Slovic, P., B. Fischhoff, and S. Lichtenstein. (1980). “Facts and Fears: Understanding Perceived Risk,” In Richard C. Schwing and Walther A. Albers, Jr. (Eds.), Societal Risk Assessment: How Safe is Safe Enough? New York: Plenum Press.Google Scholar
  36. Taylor, S. E. and S. C. Thompson (1982). “Stalking the elusive ‘vividness’ effect.” Psychological Review 89, 155–181.Google Scholar
  37. Toufexis, Anastasia (1993). “The Ultimate Choice.” Time Magazine, pp. 43–44. August 31.Google Scholar
  38. Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman (1981). “The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice,” Science 211, 243–258.Google Scholar
  39. Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman (1986). “Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions,” Journal of Business 59 (4), part 2.Google Scholar
  40. Variety (1989). “TV Reviews—Network: Everybody's Baby,” Volume 335:7, May 31.Google Scholar
  41. Viscusi, W. Kip and William N. Evans (1990). “Utility Functions That Depend on Health Status: Estimates and Economic Implications,” The American Economic Review 80 (3), 353–374.Google Scholar
  42. Viscusi, W. Kip (1992). Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Weinstein, Milton C., Donald S. Shepard, and Joseph S. Pliskin (1980). “The Economic Value of Changing Mortality Probabilities: A Decision-Theoretic Approach,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 94, 373–396.Google Scholar
  44. Whipple, Chris (1992). “Inconsistent Values in Risk Management” in Seldon Krimsky and Dominic Golding (Eds.), Social Theories of Risk. Connecticut: Praeger Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 1997

Authors and Affiliations

  • KAREN JENNI
    • 1
  • GEORGE LOEWENSTEIN
    • 2
  1. 1.Department of Engineering and Public PolicyCarnegie Mellon UniversityUSA
  2. 2.Department of Social and Decision SciencesCarnegie Mellon UniversityUSA

Personalised recommendations