Philosophical Studies

, Volume 93, Issue 1, pp 45–75 | Cite as

On the Explanatory Deficiencies of Linguistic Content

  • Bryan Frances
Article

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  1. Bach, K. (1987): Thought and Reference, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bilgrami, A. (1988):Comments on Loar 1988a, in R. Grimmand D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought, pp. 110–121, Tucson: University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bilgrami, A. (1992): Belief and Meaning, Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  4. Biro, J. (1992): ‘InDefense of SocialContent’, Philosophical Studies 67, 277–293.Google Scholar
  5. Block, N.J. (1987): ‘Functional Role and Truth Conditions’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 61, 157–181.Google Scholar
  6. Burge, T. (1979): ‘Individualism and the Mental’, in P. French, T. Uehling, Jr. and H. Wettstein (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. IV, pp. 73–122, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  7. Burge, T. (1982a): ‘Other Bodies’, in A. Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object, pp. 97–120, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Burge, T. (1982b): ‘Two Thought Experiments Reviewed’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23, 284–293.Google Scholar
  9. Burge, T. (1986): ‘Intellectual Norms and Foundations of Mind’, The Journal of Philosophy 83(12), 697–720.Google Scholar
  10. Burge, T. (1988): ‘Cartesian Error and theObjectivity of Perception’, in R. Grimm and D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought, pp. 62–76, Tucson: University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
  11. Crane, T. (1991): ‘All the Difference in the World’, The Philosophical Quarterly 41(162), 1–25.Google Scholar
  12. Davidson, D. (1987): ‘Knowing One's Own Mind’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60(3), 441–458.Google Scholar
  13. Egan, F. (1991): ‘Must Psychology be Individualistic?’, The Philosophical Review 100(2), 179–203.Google Scholar
  14. Elugardo, R. (1993): ‘Burge on Content’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53(2), 367–384.Google Scholar
  15. Fodor, J.A. (1987): Psychosemantics, Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. Fodor, J.A. (1991): ‘A Modal Argument for Narrow Content’, The Journal of Philosophy 88(1), 5–26.Google Scholar
  17. Frances, B. (1997): ‘Contradictory Belief and Epistemic Closure’, manuscript.Google Scholar
  18. Garcia Carpintero, M. (1994): ‘The Supervenience of Mental Content’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94, 117–135.Google Scholar
  19. Glock, H.J. and Preston, J. (1996): ‘Externalismand FirstPerson Authority’, The Monist 78(4), 515–533.Google Scholar
  20. Jackson, F. and Pettit, P. (1993): ‘Some Content is Narrow’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation, pp. 259–282, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Jacob, P. (1990): ‘Externalism Revisited: Is There Such a Thing as Narrow Content?’, Philosophical Studies 60, 143–176.Google Scholar
  22. Kim, J. (1984): ‘Concepts of Supervenience’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45, 153–176.Google Scholar
  23. Kim, J. (1987): ‘‘strong’ and ‘Global’ Supervenience Revisited’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48, 315–326.Google Scholar
  24. Kripke, S.A. (1980): Naming and Necessity, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Kripke, S.A. (1988): ‘A Puzzle About Belief’, in N. Salmon and S. Soames (eds.), Propositions and Attitudes, pp. 102–148, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Lewis, D. (1994): ‘Lewis, David: Reduction of Mind’, entry in Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, pp. 412–431, Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers Inc.Google Scholar
  27. Loar, B. (1987a): ‘Names in Thought’, Philosophical Studies 51, 169–185.Google Scholar
  28. Loar, B. (1987b): ‘Subjective Intentionality’, Philosophical Topics 15(1), 89–123.Google Scholar
  29. Loar, B. (1988a): ‘SocialContent and PsychologicalContent’, in R. Grimmand D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought, pp. 99–109, Tucson: University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
  30. Loar, B. (1988b): ‘Two Kinds of Content’, in R. Grimm and D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought, pp. 121–139, Tucson: University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
  31. MacDonald, C. (1990): ‘Weak Externalism and Mind-Body Identity’, Mind 99(395), 387–404.Google Scholar
  32. McKinsey, M. (1993): ‘Curing Folk Psychology of ‘Arthritis’’, Philosophical Studies 70, 323–336.Google Scholar
  33. McKinsey, M. (1994): ‘Individuating Beliefs’, in J. Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 8, pp. 303–330, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  34. Owens, J.I. (1992): ‘Psychophysical Supervenience: Its Epistemological Foundation’, Synthese 90, 89–117.Google Scholar
  35. Patterson, S. (1990): ‘The Explanatory Role of Belief Ascriptions’, Philosophical Studies 59, 313–332.Google Scholar
  36. Pereboom, D. (1995): ‘Conceptual Structure and the Individuation of Content’, in J. Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 9, pp. 401–428, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  37. Putnam, H. (1975): Mind, Language, and Reality, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Google Scholar
  38. Rudder Baker, L. (1987): Saving Belief, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Stalnaker, R.C. (1990): ‘Narrow Content’, in C.A. Anderson and J. Owens (eds.), Propositional Attitudes, pp. 131–146, Palo Alto: CSLI Press.Google Scholar
  40. Taschek, W. (1995): ‘On Belief Content and That-Clauses’, Mind and Language 10(3), 274–298.Google Scholar
  41. Taylor, K. (1995): ‘Meaning, Reference and Cognitive Significance’, Mind and Language 10(1/2), 129–180.Google Scholar
  42. Yagisawa, T. (1989): ‘The Reverse Frege Puzzle’, in Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 3, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers 1999

Authors and Affiliations

  • Bryan Frances

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations