Skip to main content
Log in

Behavioral Corporate Governance from a Regulatory Perspective: Potentials and Limits of Regulatory Intervention to Impact the Conduct of Corporate Actors

  • Articles
  • Published:
European Business Organization Law Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Usually, reflections on corporate governance take an inside perspective, i. e., a shareholder’s or a director’s point of view. Two perspectives are underrepre-sented in the discussion: firstly, an analysis from a regulatory perspective, i. e., from the government’s point of view; secondly, an analysis that draws on the recent literature on behavioral economics, experimental economics, and psychology. This paper tries to compensate for this gap in the literature.

The claim of this paper is that there is some potential for regulatory intervention to change corporate conduct by modifying the institutional design. However, this potential is limited. The paper addresses the task of institutional design by applying behavioral analysis and provides an analysis of concrete, real-world legal corporate governance institutions. It explores potentials for changing corporate conduct by accordingly shaping institutions on the basis of the foregoing behavioral analysis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. See only Joel Bakan, The Corporation (London, Constable 2004); Troy A. Paredes, ‘A Systems Approach to Corporate Governance Reform: Why Importing U.S. Corporate Law Isn’t the Answer’, 45 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. (2003–2004) p. 1055; Aulana Peters, ‘Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, Congress’ Response to Corporate Scandals: Will the New Rules Guarantee Good Governance and Avoid Future Scandals’, 28 Nova L. Rev. (2003–2004) p. 283; Robert B. Thompson, “Corporate Governance after Enron”, 40 Hous. L. Rev. (2003–2004) p. 99; Lutz-Christian Wolff, “Law as a Marketing Gimmick — The Case of the German Corporate Governance Code”, 3 Wash. U. Global Stud. L. Rev. (2004) p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Margaret M. Blair, “Shareholder Value, Corporate Governance, and Corporate Performance”, in Peter K. Cornelius and Bruce Kogut, eds., Corporate Governance and Capital Flows in a Global Economy (New York, Oxford University Press 2003) pp. 53–82; Colin F. Camerer and Ulrike Malmendier, “Behavioral Organizational Economics”, unpublished manuscript (21 June 2004) at p. 18; Donald C. Langevoort, “Managing the ‘Expectation Gap’ in Investor Protection: The SEC and the Post-Enron Reform Agenda”, 48 Vill. L. Rev. (2003) p. 1139.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See, e. g., Camerer and Malmendier, supra n. 2, at p. 4; Martin Lipton and Jay W. Lorsch, “A Modest Proposal for Improved Corporate Governance”, 48 Bus. Law. (1992–1993) p. 59 at p. 60 (arguing that improvements in corporate governance “should be developed and adopted by corporations on their own initiative and should not be imposed by legislation, regulation, court decisions overruling settled principles of corporate law, or bylaw amendments originated by institutional investors.”).

  4. See, e. g., Frank H. Easterbrook and Daniel R. Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate Law (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press 1991); Mark Roe, Strong Managers, Weak Owners: The Political Roots of American Corporate Finance (Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 1994); Eugene F. Fama and Michael C. Jensen, “Separation of Ownership and Control”, 26 J. L. & Econ. (1983) p. 301; Michael C. Jensen and William H. Meckling, “Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure”, 3 J. Fin. Econ. (1976) pp. 305–360. Not only the relationships between shareholders and managers but also those between shareholders and directors, on the one hand, and directors and managers, on the other, can be analyzed by agent models. For an analysis of the relationship between directors and managers, see James D. Cox and Harry L. Munsinger, “Bias in the Boardroom: Psychological Foundations and Legal Implications of Corporate Cohesion”, 48 L. & Contemp. Probs. (1985) p. 83; Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  5. On related topics, see, e. g., Stephen M. Bainbridge, “Why a Board? Group Decisionmaking in Corporate Governance”, 55 Vand. L. Rev. (2002) p. 1; Margaret M. Blair and Lynn A. Stout, “Trust, Trustworthiness, and the Behavioral Foundations of Corporate law”, 149 U. Pa. L. Rev. (2001) p. 1735; Cox and Munsinger, supra n. 4; Donald C. Langevoort, “The Human Nature of Corporate Boards: Law, Norms, and the Unintended Consequences of Independence and Accountability”, 89 Geo. L. J. (2001) p. 797.

    Google Scholar 

  6. The usual view of corporate governance basically accounts for the governance of the corporation from inside, i. e., by shareholders, directors, and managers. Finance theorists have argued that the central problem of corporate governance is a “principal-agent” problem, i. e., how to get corporate managers to act as loyal and committed “agents” for the shareholders or “owners” of corporations. See Jensen and Meckling, supra n. 4. See also Fama and Jensen, supra n. 4.

  7. For an overview of competing definitions of governance and how they have evolved, see Renate Mayntz, New Challenges to Governance Theory (San Domenico, Robert Schuman Centre at the European University Institute 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Public Company Accounting Reform and Investor Protection (Sarbanes-Oxley) Act, Pub. L. No. 107–204 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 15, 18 U.S.C.). Although the Sarbanes-Oxley Act is oriented to disclosure, for the most part, making it fit within the traditional concerns of federal regulation, many of its provisions go the heart of corporate governance. It contains, for instance, a bar on executive loans and comprehensive audit committee regulation. For a conservative critique, see Larry E. Ribstein, “Markets vs. Regulatory Responses to Corporate Fraud: A Critique of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002”, 28 J. Corp. L. (2002) pp. 1–67.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Easterbrook and Fischel, supra n. 4.

  10. See, e. g., Cass R. Sunstein, ed., Behavioral Law and Economics (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2000).

  11. See Camerer and Malemendier, supra n. 2, at p. 22.

  12. Donald C. Langevoort, “Organized Illusions: A Behavioral Theory of Why Corporations Mislead Stock Market Investors (and Cause Other Social Harm)”, in Sunstein, supra n. 10, p. 144 at p. 145; Paul Shrivastava, et al., “Nonrationality in Organizational Actions”, 17 Int’l Stud. Mgmt. & Org. (1987) p. 90 at p. 90 (“Organizational actions show repeated occurrence of patently nonrational behaviours. The assumption that organizations are rational entities is an unnecessary and mystifying limitation that obscures important aspects of organizing.”).

  13. See Langevoort, supra n. 12, at pp. 145–158.

  14. Such an approach to institutional design has recently been named institutional ergonomics by Martin Beckenkamp, “Institutionelle Ergonomie”, Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods (9/2004). For more on this notion, see infra section 2.1.

  15. Beckenkamp, supra n. 14.

  16. This is the definition given on the Ergonomics Society’s webpage: http://www.ergonomics.org.uk/ergonomics.htm.

  17. Beckenkamp, supra n. 14.

  18. See, e. g., Cox and Munsinger, supra n. 4; Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3.

  19. Chip Heath, et al., “Cognitive Repairs: How Organizational Practices Can Compensate for Individual Shortcomings”, 20 Res. in Org. Behav. (1998) p. 1 at p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Camerer and Malmendier, supra n. 2, at p. 24.

  21. See, e. g., Ronald J. Gilson, “Corporate Governance and Economic Efficiency: When Do Institutions Matter?”, 74 Wash. U. L. Q. (1996) p. 327 at p. 328.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., at p. 329; Blair, supra n. 2, at pp. 65–67; Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at p. 64 (“Some of the most successful companies are managed by entrepreneurs who disdain what we view as good corporate governance. Nevertheless, we are convinced that if a company is underperforming due to poor management or persisting with a failed strategy, good corporate governance is the safety valve that can provide the means to deal with the problem and improve performance.”).

  23. Path dependency means that initial conditions, determined by fortuitous events or factors traditionally viewed as non-economic, such as culture or politics, can move a system down a particular path. In a path dependent environment, the influence of factors such as increasing returns and network externalities means that an observed equilibrium may not be efficient. The more steps one takes down the path, the more difficult it may become to deviate from that path, despite the existence of alternatives that, absent transition costs, would be more efficient. See Gilson, supra n. 21, at p. 329; Michael Klausner, “Corporations, Corporate Law, and Networks of Contracts”, 81 Va. L. Rev. (1995) p. 757 at pp. 764, 772–825; J. Liebowitz and Stephen E. Margolis, “Path Dependence, Lock-In, and History”, 11 J. L. Econ. & Org. (1995) p. 205 at pp. 206–208; Mark J. Roe, “Chaos and Evolution in Law and Economics”, 109 Harv. L. Rev. (1996) p. 641 at pp. 646–653.

  24. See, e. g., A. Berle and Gardiner C. Means, The Modern Corporation and Private Property (New York, MacMillan 1932) p. 1 at pp. 3–10; Alfred D. Chandler, Scale and Scope: The Dynamics of Industrial Capitalism (Cambridge, Mass., The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press 1990) p. 2; Michael C. Jensen, “Eclipse of the Public Corporation”, Harv. Bus. Rev. (Sept.–Oct. 1989) at p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Gilson, supra n. 21, at p. 331.

  26. This is what economists call the agency problem.

  27. Gilson, supra n. 21, at p. 332.

  28. Ibid., at p. 332.

  29. Jun-Koo Kang and Anil Shivdasani, “Firm Performance, Corporate Governance, and Top Executive Turnover in Japan”, 38 J. Fin. Econ. (1995) p. 29; Stephen N. Kaplan, “Top Executive Rewards and Firm Performance: A Comparison of Japan and the United States”, 102 J. Pol. Econ. (1994) p. 510 at pp. 542–544; Stephen N. Kaplan, “Top Executives, Turnover, and Firm Performance in Germany”, 10 J. L. Econ. & Org. (1994) p. 142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Gilson, supra n. 21, at p. 340; Douglass C. North and John J. Wallis, “Integrating Institutional Change and Technical Change in Economic History. A Transaction Cost Approach”, 150 J. Inst. & Theo. Econ. (1994) p. 609.

  31. Public goods theory in this form originates in a seminal piece by Paul A. Samuelson, “The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure”, 36 Rev. Econ. & Stat. (1954) p. 387. Cornes and Sandler provide a comprehensive overview of current public good theory in Richard Cornes and Todd Sandler, The Theory of Externalities, Public Goods, and Club Goods (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1996).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Cornes and Sandler, supra n. 31, at p. 9.

  33. See ibid., at p. 347.

  34. Ibid., at p. 347.

  35. This presupposes that an individual who does not obtain a net positive effect from consumption can choose not to partake. See Yew-Kwang Ng, “The Economic Theory of Clubs: Pareto Optimal Conditions”, 40 Economica (1973) p. 291 at p. 297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. See Arthur R. Pinto, “The United States”, in Arthur R. Pinto and Gustavo Visentini, eds., The Legal Basis of Corporate Governance in Publicly Held Corporations (The Hague, Kluwer Law International 1998) p. 253 at p. 260; Cornes and Sandler, supra n. 31, at p. 347.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Cornes and Sandler, supra n. 31, at p. 394.

  38. Ibid., at p. 394.

  39. Ibid., at p. 409.

  40. Ibid., at p. 410.

  41. See Pinto supra n. 36, at p. 260 (describing the passivity of shareholders and their failure to exercise their voting rights as involving a collective action problem).

  42. Cornes and Sandler, supra n. 31, at p. 410.

  43. See also Timothy N. Cason and Vai-Lam Mui, “A Laboratory Study of Group Polarization in the Team Dictator Game”, 107 Econ. J. (1997) p. 1465 at pp. 1480–1481.

  44. See Cass R. Sunstein, Group Judgments: Deliberations, Statistical Means, and Information Markets, AEI-Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory Studies Working Paper 04–17 (September 2004).

  45. Michael C. Jensen, “The Modern Industrial Revolution, Exit, and the Failure of Internal Control Systems”, 48 J. Fin. (1993) p. 831 at p. 850. See also Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at p. 60 (“This nation needs effective means to improve performance by publicly owned companies. We believe that these means should be developed and adopted by corporations on their own initiative and should not be imposed by legislation, regulation, court decisions overruling settled principles of corporate law, or bylaw amendments originated by institutional investors.”).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. For instance, the loose coupling between regulation and behavior reminds one of Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle in physics, according to which it is not possible to predict where a particle will be with 100 percent certainty. Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle is a quantum mechanical principle that, in its most common form, states that it is not possible to simultaneously determine the position and momentum of a particle. Moreover, the better the position is known, the less well the momentum is known (and vice versa). For instance, one can say that an atom will be at some location with a 99 percent probability, but there will be a 1 percent probability it will be somewhere else (in fact, there will be a small but finite probability that it will be found across the universe). In addition, in Heisenberg’s quantum mechanical world, one can only speak in terms of probabilities. The distinction between deterministic and probabilistic approaches also exists in psychology research and theory. See, e. g., Gerd Gigerenzer, et al., “Probabilistic Mental Models: A Brunswikian Theory of Confidence”, 98 Psychol. Rev. (1991) p. 506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Christoph Engel, “Governing the Egalitarians from Without: The Case of the Internet”, Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods (10/2003) p. 20.

  48. On closer examination, almost all governance is probabilistic, not deterministic. Ibid., at p. 21.

  49. Beckenkamp, supra n. 14, at p. 21.

  50. See Julian Le Grand, Motivation, Agency and Public Policy: Of Knights and Knaves, Pawns and Queens (Oxford, Oxford University Press 2003) pp. 51–70.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  51. See supra section 2.2.2.

  52. But cf., Robert E. Lane, The Market Experience (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1991) pp. 371–374 (pointing to laboratory and field studies that show that paying people for their work may reduce their motivation, initiative, learning processes, and performances).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  53. See Langevoort, supra n. 2, at p. 1146.

  54. Ibid, at p. 1141.

  55. See ibid., at p. 1140.

  56. See Lawrence A. Cunningham, “Sharing Accounting’s Burden: Business Lawyers in Enron’s Dark Shadows”, 57 Bus. Law. (2002) p. 1421 at p. 1428 (arguing that “[i]t is hard to see what new regulations are possible. After all, regulate what? Accountants? Auditors? Executives? Boards? Politicians? Regulations are all in place.”); Ribstein, supra n. 8, at p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Langevoort, supra n. 2, at p. 1140.

  58. See Irving L. Janis, Victims of Groupthink (Atlanta, Houghton Miffrn 1972) pp. 212–213.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid., at p. 207 (explaining that the sort of psychological issues like the question how policy-makers can benefit from the cohesiveness of their group without suffering serious losses from groupthink “has been called a pretzel-shaped question and it may require pretzel-shaped answers.”).

  60. Ibid.; James Surowiecki, The Wisdom of Crowds (New York, Doubleday 2004) pp. 73-38 (“Deliberation in a groupthink setting has the disturbing effect not of opening people’s minds but of closing them.”).

  61. See Sunstein, supra n. 44 (trying to draw a more comprehensive picture of group effects from an institutional design perspective and especially addressing the question how to elicit private information from individual group members by creating “statistical groups” or “information markets”).

  62. See, e. g., Janis, supra n. 58, at p. 206 (arguing that “[u]ntil the explanation of group-think in terms of mutual support to cope with threats to self-esteem is verified by systematic research, it is risky to make huge inferential leaps from theory to the practical sphere of prevention.”).

  63. Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at p. 63 (“We propose that changes in board practices be implemented by individual boards, with no changes in laws, stock exchange rules, SEC regulations, or new court decisions. Trying to change regulations or laws will be politically difficult and at best very time consuming.”). See Sunstein, supra n. 44, at p. 39 (“Institutional leaders might reward people for disclosing information that is held by only a few; they might make clear, in advance, that departures from the prevailing wisdom are welcome.”).

  64. Janis, supra n. 58, at pp. 209–219 (making concrete suggestions for preventing group-think, most of which can only be executed by the leader of the respective group dependent on the conditions of the specific situation at issue).

  65. Langevoort, supra n. 5, at p. 831.

  66. Ibid., at p. 831.

  67. See F. Kenneth Hare, “How Should We Treat Environment?”, 167 Science (1970) p. 352 at p. 352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid.

  69. Janis, supra n. 58, at p. 208.

  70. See ibid.

  71. See Engel, supra n. 47, at p. 23.

  72. The term was coined by Lawrence Lessig and Paul Resnick, “Zoning Speech on the Internet: A Legal and Technical Model”, 98 Mich. L. Rev. (1999–2000) p. 395 at p. 423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  73. See Engel, supra n. 47, at p. 23.

  74. See Janis, supra n. 58, at p. 219 (“Recognizing that each innovation in policy-making procedures can introduce new sources of error that might be as bad as or worse than group-think, we can see why public administrators and executives in large private organizations might have solid reasons for resisting any change in their standard procedures.”).

  75. John M. Clark, “Toward a Concept of Workable Competition”, 30 Am. Econ. Rev. (1940) p. 241 at pp. 242–243.

    Google Scholar 

  76. See Bainbridge, supra n. 5, at p. 21 (“An actor can economize limited cognitive resources in two ways: first, by adopting institutional governance structures designed to promote more efficient decision-making, and second, by invoking shortcuts, i. e., heuristic problem-solving decision-making processes.”).

  77. Gilson, supra n. 21, at p. 340. See also Rebecca M. Henderson and Kim B. Clark, “Architectural Innovation: The Reconfiguration of Existing Product Technologies and the Failure of Established Firms”, 35 Admin. Sci. Q. (1990) p. 9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  78. Gilson, supra n. 21, at p. 341.

  79. See Ronald J. Gilson, “The Political Ecology of Takeovers: Thoughts on Harmonizing the European Corporate Governance Environment”, 61 Fordham L. Rev. (1992) p. 161 at pp. 174–175.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Gilson, supra n. 21, at p. 342.

  81. See Shlomo Benartzi and Richard H. Thaler, “Naive Diversification Strategies in Defined Contribution Saving Plans”, 91 American Economic Review (2001) p. 79 at p. 96; David S. Scharfstein and Jeremy C. Stein, “The Dark Side of Internal Capital Markets: Divisional Rent Seeking and Inefficient Investment”, 55 J. Fin. (2000) pp. 2537–2564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  82. See Neil D. Weinstein, “Unrealistic Optimism About Future Life Events”, 39 J. Personality & Soc. Psychol. (1980) pp. 806–820; Shelly E. Taylor and Jonathan D. Brown, “Illusion and Well-Being: A Social Psychological Perspective on Mental Health”, 103 Psychol. Bull. (1988) pp. 193–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  83. Dorwin Cartwright, “The Nature of Group Cohesiveness”, in Dorwin Cartwright and Alvin Zander, eds., Group Dynamics. Research and Theory (New York, Harper and Row 1968) pp. 91–109 (defining group cohesiveness as “the degree to which the members of a group desire to remain in the group”); Leon Festinger, “Informal Social Communication”, in Cartwright and Zander, ibid., p. 182 at p. 185 (defining group cohesiveness as “the resultant of all the forces acting on the members to remain in the group”); See also Hans Werner Bierhoff, Sozialpsychologie, 4th edn. (Stuttgart, Kohlhammer 1998) p. 285 (defining group cohesiveness as “Bindung an die Gruppe”).

    Google Scholar 

  84. See, e. g., Karl E. Weick and Karlene H. Roberts, “Collective Mind in Organizations: Heedful Interrelating on Flight Decks”, 38 Admin. Sci. Q. (1993) p. 357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  85. See ibid., at p. 357.

  86. See, e. g., Walter Schneider and Richard M. Shiffrin, “Controlled and Automatic Human Information Processing: I. Detection, Search, and Attention”, 84 Psychol. Rev. (1977) p. 1 at p. 51 (distinguishing between automatic information sprocessing, which is learned in long-term store, and controlled information processing, which is a temporary activation of nodes in a sequence that is not yet learned and requires attention).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. See Gilber Ryle, The Concept of Mind (Chicago, University of Chicago Press 1949).

    Google Scholar 

  88. Weick and Roberts, supra n. 84, at p. 360.

  89. Ibid., at p. 365.

  90. See ibid., at p. 366.

  91. Ibid., at p. 368.

  92. Surowiecki, supra n. 60, at p. xix.

  93. Ibid.

  94. Ibid., at p. xx.

  95. Janis, supra n. 58, at pp. 209–219.

  96. Ibid., at p. 209.

  97. Ibid., at p. 214.

  98. Ibid., at p. 215.

  99. Ibid., at p. 218.

  100. Surowiecki, supra n. 60, at p. 209.

  101. Ibid.

  102. Ibid., at p. 210.

  103. Ibid., at pp. 220–222.

  104. Ibid., at pp. 241–258.

  105. See Klaus C. Engelen, “Preventing European ‘Enronitis’”, 18 Int’l. Econ. (2004) p. 40 at p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  106. 17 C.F.R. § 240.10b-5 Employment of Manipulative and Deceptive Devices (General Rules and Regulations promulgated under the Securities Exchange Act of 1934).

  107. Ernst & Ernst v. Hochfelder et al., 425 U.S. 185, 214 (1976) (holding that “[w]hen a statute speaks so specifically in terms of manipulation and deception, and of implementing devices and contrivances — the commonly understood terminology of intentional wrongdoing — and when its history reflects no more expansive intent, we are quite unwilling to extend the scope of the statute to negligent conduct”); Santa Fe Indus, v. Green, 430 U.S. 462, 473 (1977) (arguing that “[t]he language of § 10(b) gives no indication that Congress meant to prohibit any conduct not involving manipulation or deception.”); Aaron v. SEC, 446 U.S. 680, 701–02 (1980) (holding that the SEC “is required to establish scienter as an element of a civil enforcement action to enjoin violations of § 17(a)(1) of the 1933 Act, § 10(b) of the 1934 Act, and Rule 10b-5 promulgated under that section of the 1934 Act.”).

  108. Eberhard Schwark, in Eberhard Schwark, ed., Kapitalmarktrechtskommentar, 3rd edn. (Munich, Beck 2004) § 20a WpHG at pp. 44–45.

  109. See Pressemitteilung des Bundesgerichthofs No. 87/2004 of 19 July 2004 and BGH II ZR 217/03, BGH II ZR 218/03, and BGH II ZR 402/02.

  110. Langevoort, supra n. 12, at p. 157.

  111. Ibid., at p. 157.

  112. See supra section 2.3.3.

  113. James D. Cox, et al., Securities Regulation, 4th edn. (New York, Aspen 2004) p. 629.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Steve Thel, “The Original Conception of Section 10(b) of the Securities Exchange Act”, 42 Stan. L. Rev. (1990) p. 385 at pp. 388–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  115. Cox et al., supra n. 113, at p. 630.

  116. The Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 has brought about a reform of the accounting standards in the United States. See supra n. 8.

  117. Donald C. Langevoort, “The Organizational Psychology of Hyper-Competition: Corporate Irresponsibility and the Lessons of Enron”, 70 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. (2002) p. 968 at pp. 968 and 975.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Ibid., at pp. 969–971.

  119. Pinto, supra n. 36, at pp. 258–259.

  120. Patrik C. Leyens, “Deutscher Aufsichtsrat und U.S.-Board: ein- oder zweistufiges Verwaltungssystem?”, 67 RabelsZ (2003) p. 57 at p. 71; Pinto, supra n. 36, atp. 261.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Ibid., at pp. 57, 71.

  122. Reinier Kraakman, “Die Professionalisierung des Boards”, in Dieter Feddersen, et al., eds., Corporate Governance — Optimierung der Unternehmensführung und der Unternehmenskontrolle im deutschen und amerikanischen Aktienrecht (Cologne, Otto Schmidt 1996) p. 129 atp. 139.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Ibid., atp. 139.

  124. See Colin F. Camerer and Dan Lovallo, “Overconfidence and Excess Entry: An Experimental Approach”, 89 Am. Econ. Rev. (1999) p. 306 at pp. 314–315. See also Arnold C. Cooper, et al., “Entrepreneurs’ Perceived Chances for Success”, 3 J. Bus. Venturing (1988) p. 97 at p. 103; Ellen J. Langer, “The Illusion of Control”, 32 J. Personality & Soc. Psychol. (1975) p. 311 at p. 327 (finding that the more similar a chance situation is to a skill situation in outcome-independent ways, the greater will be the illusion of control, and the individual will be more confident and more likely to take risks); Laurie Larwood and William Whittaker, “Managerial Myopia: Self-Serving Biases in Organizational Planning”, 62 J. Applied Psychol. (1977) p. 194 at p. 198 (finding that there is a general belief among managers and students of management that their own firms would possess unusually high growth rates due to their managing abilities); James G. March and Zur Shapira, “Managerial Perspectives on Risk and Risk Taking”, 33 Mgmt. Sci. (1987) p. 1404 at pp. 1411, 1414 (finding that most managers fail to follow the canons of decision theory, that the ways they think about risk are not easily fit into classical theoretical conceptions of risk, and that they believe that they can do better than is expected, even after the estimates have been revised).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  125. See, e. g., Jensen, supra n. 45, at pp. 863–865 (suggesting that the only inside board member should be the CEO).

  126. Langevoort, supra n. 5, at p. 797.

  127. For a review of the finance literature, see only Sanjai Bhagat and Bernhard Black, “The Uncertain Relationship between Board Composition and Firm Performance”, 54 Bus. Law. (1999) p. 921 at pp. 921–922.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Ibid., at p. 950.

  129. Langevoort, supra n. 5, at p. 807.

  130. Cox and Munsinger, supra n. 4.

  131. Janis, supra n. 58; Surowiecki, supra n. 60, at pp. 73–38 (“Deliberation in a groupthink setting has the disturbing effect not of opening people’s minds but of closing them.”).

  132. Langevoort, supra n. 5, at pp. 810–811.

  133. See Bhagat and Black, supra n. 127, at pp. 941–942; Theodor Eisenberg, et al., “Larger Board Size and Decreasing Firm Value in Small Firms”, 48 J. Fin. Econ. (1998) p. 35 at p. 36; Jensen, supra n. 45, at p. 865; Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at pp. 65, 67–68; David Yermak, “Higher Market Valuation of Companies with a Small Board of Directors”, 40 J. Fin. Econ. (1996) p. 185 at pp. 186–87. See also Tatsuya Kameda, et al., “Social Dilemmas, Subgroups, and Motivational Loss in Task-Oriented Groups: In Search of an ’Optimal’ Team Size in Division of Work”, 55 Soc. Psychol. Q. (1992) p. 47. Contra Bainbridge, supra n. 5, at pp. 42–44 (arguing mainly in favor of larger boards); Dan R. Dalton, et al., “Number of Directors and Financial Performance: A Meta-Analysis”, 42 Acad. Mgmt. J. (1999) p. 674 (arguing on the basis of a meta-analysis that a statistically significant correlation between increased board size and improved financial performance can be found); Paul B. Firstenberg and Burton G. Malkiel, “The Twenty-First Century Boardroom: Who Will Be in Charge?”, 36 Sloan Mgmt. Rev. (1994) p. 27 at p. 34 (“We are not persuaded that the advantages of a small board outweigh those of a somewhat larger one of perhaps twelve or even eighteen members, at least for a large, publicly traded corporation. A very small board can defeat the objective of encouraging a wide range of views. Moreover, a size constraint can limit the board members’ varied experiences and potential diversity of race, gender, and geographical distribution.”).

  134. Business Roundtable, Statement on Corporate Governance 10 (September 1997), available at: http://www.brt.org. The number of directors is usually set in the by-laws or certificate, and they elected by the shareholders at their annual meeting.

  135. National Association of Corporate Directors (NACD), Public Company Governance Survey 1999–2000 (October 2000) at p. 7 (44 percent between seven and nine members).

  136. Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at p. 64.

  137. Ibid., at p. 64.

  138. See Klaus J. Hopt, “The German Two-Tier Board: Experience, Theories, Reforms”, in Klaus J. Hopt, et al., eds., Comparative Corporate Governance. The State of The Art and Emerging Research (Oxford, Clarendon Press 1998) p. 227 at pp. 241–42; Leyens, supra n. 120, at p. 81. However, this is different in the coal and steel industry where special provisions apply.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Gesetz über die Mitbestimmung der Arbeitnehmer vom 4.5.1976, BGBl. I, S. 1153. In smaller corporations, employees get one third of the positions on the council.

  140. Leyens, supra n. 120, at pp. 81–82.

  141. Ibid., at pp. 81–82. § 110 AktG obliges the supervisory council to have a session twice a year.

  142. Wolfgang Bernhardt, “Aufsichtsrat — die schönste Nebensache der Welt?”, 195 ZHR (1995) p. 310 at pp. 311–312; Hopt, supra n. 138; Manuel R. Theisen, “Empirical Evidence and Economic Comments on Board Structure in Germany”, in Hopt et al., supra n. 138, p. 259 at pp. 261–262.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Martina Deckert, “Effektive Überwachung der AG-Geschäftsführung durch Ausschüsse des Aufsichtsrates”, 17 ZIP (1996) p. 985 at pp. 989–992; Marcus Lutter, “Vergleichende Corporate Governance — Die deutsche Sicht”, 30 ZGR (2001) p. 224 at pp. 227–237.

    Google Scholar 

  144. See, e. g., Bernhardt, supra n. 142, at p. 316. Note that according to § 100 II No. 1 AktG, one individual is not allowed to be a member of more than ten supervisory councils at the same time.

  145. Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at p. 69 (“Boards should meet at least bimonthly and each meeting should take a full day, including committee sessions and other related activities. One meeting each year should be a two or three day strategy session.”).

  146. Jensen, supra n. 45, at p. 866; Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at p. 70.

  147. Langevoort, supra n. 117, at p. 972.

  148. Langevoort, supra n. 12, at p. 156.

  149. French law also contemplates employee participation, but only as an optional feature. In contrast, US law is completely silent on this issue. Proposals for the creation of labor directors emerge consistently in the United States.

  150. Gesetz über die Mitbestimmung der Arbeitnehmer vom 4.5.1976, BGBl. I, S. 1153. In smaller corporations, employees get one third of the positions on the council; see Klaus J. Hopt, “Gemeinsame Grundsätze der Corporate Governance in Europa?”, 29 ZGR (2000) p. 779 at pp. 800–802.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  151. Kent Greenfield, “The Place of Workers in Corporate law”, 39 B.C.L.Rev. (1998) p. 283 at p. 287; Marleen A. O’Connor, “The Human Capital Era: Reconceptualizing Corporate Law to Facilitate Labor-Management Cooperation”, 78 Cornell L. Rev. (1993) p. 899.

    Google Scholar 

  152. O’Connor, supra n. 151, at pp. 961–965.

  153. See supra n. 97 and accompanying text.

  154. See Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, 18 September 2004, at p. 11.

  155. See Rakesh Khurana, “Vorstände sollten ihre Gehälter nicht offen legen”, Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, 23 August 2004, at p. 14.

  156. In the United States, independent directors can also be compensated by means of stock options. See Lipton and Lorsch, supra n. 3, at p. 69. In contrast to this, the German Federal Supreme Court (Bundesgerichtshof) has recently decided that the directors of the supervisory board (who are comparable to outside directors under US law) are no longer allowed to receive stock options as part of their compensation. See BGH II ZR 316/02 of 16 February 2004 (holding that the stock options’ value depends on the stock price, which can be affected by well-directed arrangements of circumstances of the management in a legal or illegal way, and that the stock price is not always a reliable benchmark for the internal value and the long-term success of a firm. The court thus sees compensation that consists at least partly of stock options as a threat to the control function of the supervisory board.).

  157. See only Jensen supra n. 45, at pp. 864–865.

  158. See Weinstein, supra n. 82, at p. 814.

  159. Simon Gervais, et al., Overconfidence, Investment, Policy and Stock Options, unpublished working paper (24 July 2003) at pp. 22–23, 27, available at: http://faculty.haas.berkeley.edu/odean/papers/Managers/GervaisHeatonOdean0703.pdf.

  160. Camerer and Malmendier, supra n. 2, at p. 34.

  161. Ibid., at p. 34.

  162. See Janis, supra n. 58, at p. 206 (“Until the explanation of groupthink in terms of mutual support to cope with threats of self-esteem is verified by systematic research, it is risky to make huge inferential leaps from theory to the practical sphere of prevention. Ultimately, a well-substantiated theory should have valuable practical applications to the formulation of effective prescriptions. … But until we know we have a good theory — one that is well supported by controlled experiments and systematic correlational research, as well as by case studies — we must recognize that any prescriptions we draw up are speculative inferences based on what little we know, or think we know, about when and why groupthink occurs. Still, we should not be inhibited from drawing tentative inferences — so long as we label them as such — in order to call attention to potentially useful means of prevention.”).

  163. See Janis, supra n. 58, at p. 208.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kordel, G. Behavioral Corporate Governance from a Regulatory Perspective: Potentials and Limits of Regulatory Intervention to Impact the Conduct of Corporate Actors. Eur Bus Org Law Rev 9, 29–62 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1017/S1566752908000293

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1566752908000293

Keywords

Navigation