Skip to main content
Log in

What is an aesthetic concept?

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Asian Journal of Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Aesthetic concepts and conceptions are structured mental representations partly composed of phenomenal concepts. I defend this claim by appealing to contemporary accounts of concepts and to the current literature on phenomenal concepts. In addition, I discuss the relationship between aesthetic concepts and aesthetic understanding — an epistemic state at the centre of much work in contemporary epistemology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this essay, by ‘conscious’ or ‘consciousness’, I mean primarily ‘phenomenally conscious’ or ‘phenomenal consciousness’, respectively.

  2. I will employ the convention of referring to concepts by using low capital letters.

  3. Levinson (2005: 11–2) claims that Sibley’s work is the starting point of contemporary work on aesthetic properties (not concepts), as does Stecker (2010: chapter 4). Another popular line of inquiry in the contemporary debate is focused on aesthetic terms, see Marques (2016) for a recent account.

  4. Beardsley (1982), Matthen (2017), Nanay (2016).

  5. See Laurence & Margolis (1999, 2013) for recent surveys of the contemporary literature on the nature of concepts.

  6. Some recent works on the notion of understanding include Kvanvig (2003), Pritchard (2009, 2010), Sliwa (2015) and Hills (2016). See Hannon (2021) for a recent overview.

  7. One influential account of phenomenal concepts is proposed in many of Brian Loar’s papers: Loar (1997/2017, 2003). See also Balog (1999, 2009, 2012), Papineau (2002, 2007), Tye (2003), Levin (2007) and Diaz-Leon (2016). Michael Tye recanted his 2003 account in Tye (2009).

  8. See Sterelny (1990), Ryder (2009) and Von Eckardt (2012) for introductions to the notion of a mental representation and to the representational theory of mind, which I will assume in this paper.

  9. The idea that concepts are mental representations plays a central role in contemporary cognitive science (Carey 2009; Fodor 1998). Peacocke (1992) defends the view that concepts are Fregean senses, abstract entities that can be combined in the form of propositional contents expressed by thoughts.

  10. See Fodor & Phylyshyn (1988). Johnson (2004) offers compelling reasons to believe that the debate suffers of a serious problem because the same concept of systematicity is at best unclear.

  11. My understanding of conception derives from Bengson (2015, 2018).

  12. I am not claiming that a conception and its properties are the mere sum of its concepts and their properties, as other factors (e.g., relational properties) may determine the properties of the conception (e.g., the coherence of the concepts involved).

  13. See Bermudez (2003) and Camp (2009) for discussion.

  14. There are other accounts of the nature of phenomenal concepts, for example, David Papineau’s Quotational model — see Papineau (2002, 2007: 116–9) for further discussion. However, for reasons of space, I will not discuss them in this paper.

  15. Some have argued that phenomenal concepts do not exist because the Experience Condition clashes with other plausible conditions or views (Tye 2009). I do not find these arguments convincing, and I will assume that the replies already offered by others are successful in deflecting such criticisms (e.g., Veillet 2012 and Diaz-Leon 2016).

  16. On aesthetic understanding, see also Hills (2018, 2022). One of the differences between my account and Hills’ is that mine deploys the notions of aesthetic concept and conception. On the relationship between understanding and grasping, see Elgin (2017) and Baumberger and Brun (2017). In this paper, I will take the notion of grasping as primitive. Grasping reveals itself in cases in which we grasp an explanation in a way that satisfies relationships of coherence among the various elements of such an explanation (Riggs 2003: 217).

  17. Similar ideas — ideas about the explanatory role of the relationship between aesthetic and non-aesthetic properties for ascriptions of aesthetic value — have been discussed by many aestheticians and philosophers of art; for example, Sibley (1965, 1974) Beardsley (1974), Levinson (2005) and Zangwill (2001, 2007), Sauchelli (2022).

  18. See Heathwood (2007) and Aydede (2018) for recent general discussions on pleasure, and Levinson (1992) and Matthen (2017) for aesthetic pleasure.

  19. One attempt to define a formal property is offered by Nick Zangwill: ‘I shall stipulate that the word “narrow” includes both sensory properties, nonrelational physical properties, and also any dispositions to provoke responses that might be thought to be partly constitutive of aesthetic properties. The word “broad” covers anything else. So, we can blandly say: Formal properties are entirely determined by narrow nonaesthetic properties, whereas nonformal aesthetic properties are partly determined by broad nonaesthetic properties’ (Zangwill 2001: 57). See also Budd (1995: 52), Wollheim (2001) and Nanay (2016) for discussion and alternative proposals.

  20. See De Clercq (2008: 902–4) for discussion on the connection between response-dependence and aesthetic properties.

  21. See Jackson (1982) and Loar (1997) for two seminal papers on the thought experiment in question.

  22. Unity is here intended as a form of sensed congruity among the elements of a design, that is, a property that the elements of the design have when they appear as having a non-random connection.

  23. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this point.

  24. See Carey (2009) for an account of the origin and development of concepts.

  25. See Stecker (2012) for a recent defence of the distinction between aesthetic and artistic value.

References

  • Aydede, M. (2018). A contemporary account of sensory pleasure. In L. Shapiro (Ed.), Pleasure: A history (pp. 239–266). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balog, K. (1999). Conceivability, possibility, and the mind-body problem. Philosophical Review, 108(4), 497–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balog, K. (2009). Phenomenal concepts. In B. McLaughlin, et al. (Eds.), Oxford handbook in the philosophy of mind (pp. 292–312). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Balog, K. (2012). In Defence of the phenomenal concept strategy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumberger, C., & Brun, G. (2017). Dimensions of objectual understanding. In S. Grimm, et al. (Eds.), Explaining understanding (pp. 165–189). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beardsley, M. (1974). The descriptivist account of aesthetic attributions. Revue Internationale De Philosophie, 28, 336–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beardsley, M. (1982). The aesthetic point of view. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2015). A noetic theory of understanding and intuition as sense-maker. Inquiry, 58(7), 633–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2018). The unity of understanding. In S. Grimm (Ed.), Making sense of the world (pp. 14–53). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. (2003). Thinking without words. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Budd, M. (1995). Values of art. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Budd, M. (2006). The characterisation of aesthetic qualities by essential metaphors and quasi-metaphors. British Journal of Aesthetics, 46(2), 133–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspective, 21, 145–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2009). Putting thoughts to work. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78(2), 275–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2015). Logical concepts and associative characterizations. In The conceptual mind (pp. 591–621). The MIT Press.

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Clercq, R. (2008). The structure of aesthetic properties. Philosophy Compass, 3(5), 894–909.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diaz-Leon, E. (2016). Phenomenal concepts: Neither circular nor opaque. Philosophical Psychology, 29(8), 1186–1199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2017). True enough. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture. Cognition, 28, 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hannon, M. (2021). Recent work in the epistemology of understanding. American Philosophical Quarterly, 58(3), 269–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, C. (2007). The reduction of sensory pleasure to desire. Philosophical Studies, 133, 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2016). Understanding why. Noûs, 50(4), 661–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2018). Aesthetic understanding. In S. Grimm (Ed.), Making sense of the world (pp. 159–176). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2022). Aesthetic testimony, understanding and virtue. Noûs, 56(1), 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, K. (2004). On the systematicity of language and thought. Journal of Philosophy, 101(3), 111–139.

  • Kriegel, U. (2015). The varieties of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, Stephen & Eric Margolis. (1999). Concepts and cognitive science. In Concepts: Core readings, 3–81. The MIT Press.

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (2013). The scope of the conceptual. In R. Samuels, et al., (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of cognitive science (pp. 291–317). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, J. (2007). What is a phenomenal concept? In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge (pp. 87–110). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. (1992). Pleasure and the value of works of art. British Journal of Aesthetics, 32(4), 295–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. (2005/2006). What are aesthetic properties? Reprinted in his Contemplating art (pp. 336–353). Clarendon Press.

  • Loar, B. (1997/2017). Phenomenal states: Second version. Reprinted in his Consciousness and meaning: Selected essays (pp. 195–219). Oxford University Press.

  • Loar, B. (2003/2017). Transparent experience and the availability of qualia. Reprinted in his Consciousness and meaning: Selected essays (pp. 273–290). Oxford University Press.

  • Loar, B. (2003). Qualia, properties, modality. Philosophical Issues, 13, 113–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marques, T. (2016). Aesthetic predicates: A hybrid dispositional account. Inquiry, 59(6), 723–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2017). The pleasure of art. Australasian Philosophical Review, 1(1), 6–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–456.

  • Nanay, B. (2016). Aesthetics as philosophy of perception. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2007). Phenomenal and perceptual concepts. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge (pp. 111–144). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge, understanding and epistemic value. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64. Cambridge University Press.

  • Pritchard, D. (2010). Knowledge and understanding. In D. Pritchard, A. Millar, & A. Haddock (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge (pp. 3–88). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, W. (2003). Understanding ‘virtue’ and the virtue of understanding. In M. De Paul, et al. (Eds.), Intellectual virtue (pp. 203–226). Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, D. (2009). Problems of Representation I: Nature and Role. In Symons, J., & Calvo, P. (Eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology (pp. 233–50). Routledge.

  • Sauchelli, A. (2014). Horror and mood. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51(1), 39–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauchelli, A. (2022). Aesthetic realism and manifest properties. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 80(2), 201–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sibley, F. (1959/2001). Aesthetic concepts. Reprinted in his Approach to aesthetics (pp. 1–23). Clarendon Press.

  • Sibley, F. (1965/2001). Aesthetic and non-aesthetic. Reprinted in his Approach to aesthetics (pp. 33–51). Clarendon Press.

  • Sibley, F. (1974/2001). Particularity, art, and evaluation. Reprinted in his Approach to aesthetics (pp. 88–103). Clarendon Press.

  • Sliwa, P. (2015). Understanding and knowing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 115(1), 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stecker, R. (2010). Aesthetics and philosophy of art, 2nd edition. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.

  • Stecker, R. (2012). Artistic value defended. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 70(4), 355–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1990) The representational theory of mind. Basil Blackwell.

  • Tye, M. (2003). A theory of phenomenal concepts. Philosophy, 53, 91–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2009). Consciousness revisited. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veillet, B. (2012). In defense of phenomenal concepts. Philosophical Papers, 41(1), 97–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veryzer, R. W., & Hutchinson, J. W. (1998). The influence of unity and prototypicality on aesthetic responses to new product designs. Journal of Consumer Research, 24(4), 374–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Eckardt, B. (2012). The representational theory of mind. In Frankish, K., & Ramsey, W. (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Cognitive Science (pp. 29–49). Cambridge University Press.

  • Wollheim, R. (2001). On formalism and pictorial organization. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 59, 127–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, T.-Y., et al. (2017). Unity enhances product aesthetics and emotion. International Journal of Industrial Ergonomics, 59, 92–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (2001). The metaphysics of beauty. Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (2007). Aesthetic creation. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (2014). Music, metaphor, and aesthetic concepts. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 72(1), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Sauchelli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sauchelli, A. What is an aesthetic concept?. AJPH 1, 35 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-022-00037-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-022-00037-z

Keywords

Navigation