Abstract
According to Satosi Watanabe’s “theorem of the ugly duckling”, the number of predicates satisfied by any two different particulars is a constant, which does not depend on the choice of the two particulars. If the number of predicates satisfied by two particulars is their number of properties in common, and the degree of resemblance between two particulars is a function of their number of properties in common, then it follows that the degree of resemblance between any two different particulars is also constant, which is absurd. Avoiding this absurd conclusion requires questioning assumptions about infinity in the proof or interpretation of the theorem, adopting a sparse conception of properties, or denying degree of resemblance is a function of number of properties in common. After arguing against both the first two options, this paper argues for a version of the third which analyses degree of resemblance as a function of properties in common, but weighted by their degree of naturalness or importance.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
The name “abundant” comes from Lewis (1983, p. 346); see also Lewis (1986b, p. 59). Some writers prefer “deflationary”, following Hale, who writes “According to the abundant or, as I prefer to call it, deflationary conception of properties, every meaningful predicate stands for a property or relation, and it is sufficient for the actual existence of a property or relation that there could be a predicate with appropriate satisfaction conditions” (Hale , 2013, p. 132); see also Cook (2019) and Hale (2015). I prefer “abundant” not only because of the contrast with “sparse”, but also because I do not wish to imply that, according to the abundant conception, properties are any less real or fundamental.
For analyses of degree of dissimilarity as a function of number of properties in common and not in common see, for example, Niiniluoto (1987, pp. 22–35), Oliver (1996, p. 52), Rodriguez-Pereyra (2002, pp. 65–69), Paseau (2012, p. 365), Blumson (2014b, pp. 179–193), Paseau (2015, p. 110), Blumson (2018), and Blumson (2019b). Yi (2018) criticises some of these analyses. For scepticism of whether resemblance is measurable by numerical degree at all, see Lewis (1973, p. 50), Williamson (1988, pp. 457–460), Blumson (2019a), and Paseau (2020); for defence see, for example, Bigelow (1976, 1977), Tversky (1977), Suppes et al. (1989, pp. 159–225), Weisberg (2012), Kroedel and Huber (2013, pp. 459–462), and Enflo (2020). Section 4 is also a partial defence of this presupposition. Morreau (2010) argues against the cogency of overall comparative similarity on different grounds.
The argument is also raised outside metaphysics by, amongst others, Towster (1975), Watanabe (1985), Oddie (1986, pp. 164–165), Niiniluoto (1987, pp. 35–37), Medin et al. (1993, p. 255), Mundy (1995, pp. 35–36), Feldman (1997, p. 150), Byrne (2003, p. 641), Priest (2008, p. 97), Sterrett (2009, p. 803), Decock and Douven (2011, p. 68), Isaac (2013, p. 685), Blumson (2014b, pp. 182-196), Ott (2016, pp. 140-141), and Harnad (2017, pp. 36–37). Most of these authors stress the infinite case, and many draw radical conclusions.
For a related point see, for example, Oddie (2005, pp. 151–152).
For a related point see, for example, Oddie (2005, pp. 151–152).
Note that an “atom” in this context is not a syntactically simple predicate: ‘lands’, for example, is not an atom, because it is strictly entailed by ‘lands one’, whereas ‘lands on an even number and lands on a prime number’ is an atom, because it is strictly entailed by ‘does not land’ but not by any other predicate. Atoms are akin to Sider’s “profiles” (1993, p. 50); see also Dorr and Hawthorne (2013, p. 23).
In contrast to predicates in the infinitary languages discussed by Cook (2019).
Bjerring and Schwarz (2017, p. 26) make a similar point about analysing propositions as sets of worlds.
Gardenfors (2000, pp. 59–100) and Oddie (2005, pp. 152–158), for example, present a sparse conception of properties which is like Armstrong’s in accepting that all conjunctions of sparse properties are properties, but differs from Armstrong’s in only denying that some negative and disjunctive properties are. But Blumson (2019b) proves this conception does not overcome the problems with Armstrong’s.
Although no conceptions in the literature correspond exactly to this conception, some are just as unremittingly sparse. According to Rodriguez-Pereyra (2002, pp. 48–52), for example, the sparse properties are “lowest determinate properties”, and there are no negative, conjunctive or disjunctive sparse properties. I intend to consider Rodriguez-Pereyra’s theory in more detail elsewhere.
The name “ultra-additivity” comes from Skyrms (1983, 227).
This problem, suggested by anonymous referee, generalises objections to Rodriguez-Pereyra (2002) given by Yi (2018). Blumson (2018, pp. 34–36) also raises similar problems of infinity for the analysis of degree of similarity as proportion of properties in common, some of which generalise to analysis of degree of similarity as weighted proportion of properties in common. I intend to take this up again elsewhere.
References
Armstrong, D. (1978a). Nominalism and Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Armstrong, D. (1978b). A Theory of Universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Armstrong, D. (1989). Universals. Boulder: Westview Press.
Bacon, J. (1986). Armstrong’s Theory of Properties. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 47–53.
Benacerraf, P. (1962). Tasks, Super-Tasks, and the Modern Eleatics. The Journal of Philosophy, 59, 765–784.
Bigelow, J. (1976). Possible Worlds Foundations for Probability. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5, 299–320.
Bigelow, J. (1977). Semantics of Probability. Synthese, 36, 459–472.
Bjerring, J. C., & Schwarz, W. (2017). Granularity Problems. The Philosophical Quarterly, 67, 22–37.
Blumson, B. (2014a). A Never-Ending Story. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 14, 111–120.
Blumson, B. (2014b). Resemblance and Representation. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers.
Blumson, B. (2015). Story Size. Philosophical Papers, 44, 121–137.
Blumson, B. (2018). Two Conceptions of Similarity. The Philosophical Quarterly, 68, 21–37.
Blumson, B. (2019a). Distance and Dissimilarity. Philosophical Papers, 48, 211–239.
Blumson, B. (2019b). Naturalness and Convex Class Nominalism. Dialectica, 73, 65–81.
Byrne, A. (2003). Color and Similarity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 641–665.
Collins, J. (2010). How Long Can a Sentence Be and Should Anyone Care? Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 10, 199–207.
Cook, R. T. (2019). Possible predicates and actual properties. Synthese, 196, 2555–2582.
Cowling, S. (2017). Resemblance. Philosophy. Compass, 12, 1–11.
Davey, B. A., & Priestley, H. A. (2002). Introduction to Lattices and Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Decock, L., & Douven, I. (2011). Similarity After Goodman. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 61–75.
Dorr, C., & Hawthorne, J. (2013). Naturalness. In K. Bennett, & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics (pp. 2–77). Oxford: Oxford University Press volume 8.
Enflo, K. (2020). Measures of Similarity. Theoria, 86, 73–99.
Feldman, J. (1997). The Structure of Perceptual Categories. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 41, 145–170.
Field, H. (2004). The Consistency of the Naïve Theory of Properties. Philosophical Quarterly, 54, 78–104.
Gardenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Goodman, N. (1972). Seven Strictures on Similarity. In Problems and Projects. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merril.
Gratzer, G. (2011). Lattice Theory: Foundation. Basel: Springer.
Guigon, G. (2014). Overall Similarity, Natural Properties, and Paraphrases. Philosophical Studies, 167, 387–399.
Hale, B. (2013). Properties and the Interpretation of Second-Order Logic. Philosophia Mathematica, 21, 133–156.
Hale, B. (2015). Second-Order Logic: Properties, Semantics, and Existential Commitments. Synthese, (pp. 1–27).
Harnad, S. (2017). To Cognize is to Categorize. Handbook of Categorization in Cognitive Science (pp. 21–54). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Isaac, A. M. C. (2013). Objective Similarity and Mental Representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 683–704.
Kroedel, T., & Huber, F. (2013). Counterfactual Dependence and Arrow. Nous, 47, 453–466.
Langendoen, D. T., & Postal, P. M. (1986). The Vastness of Natural Languages. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lewis, D. (1983). New Work for a Theory of Universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.
Lewis, D. (1986a). Against Structural Universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 25–46.
Lewis, D. (1986b). On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.
Maclaurin, J., & Sterelny, K. (2008). What Is Biodiversity? Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Medin, D. L., Goldstone, R. L., & Gentner, D. (1993). Respects for Similarity. Psychological Review, 100, 254.
Morreau, M. (2010). It Simply Does Not Add Up: Trouble with Overall Similarity. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 469–490.
Mundy, J. L. (1995). Object Recognition: The Search for Representation. In M. Hebert, J. Ponce, T. Boult, & A. Gross (Eds.), Object Representation in Computer Vision Lecture Notes in Computer Science (pp. 19–50). Berlin Heidelberg: Springer.
Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Oddie, G. (1986). Likeness to Truth. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Oddie, G. (2005). Value, Reality, and Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Oliver, A. (1996). The Metaphysics of Properties. Mind, 105, 1–80.
Ott, W. (2016). Phenomenal Intentionality and the Problem of Representation. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2, 131–145.
Paseau, A. (2012). Resemblance Theories of Properties. Philosophical Studies, 157, 361–382.
Paseau, A. (2015). Six Similarity Theories of Properties. In G. Guigon & G. Rodriguez-Pereya (Eds.), Nominalism about Properties. New York: Routledge.
Paseau, A. C. (2020). Non-metric Propositional Similarity. Erkenntnis.
Priest, G. (2008). From If to Is: An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Quinton, A. (1957). Properties and Classes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 58, 33–58.
Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance Nominalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Russell, B. (1918). The Philosophy of Logical Atomism [with Discussion]. The Monist, 28, 495–527.
Schaffer, J. (2004). Two Conceptions of Sparse Properties. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 85, 92–102.
Sider, T. (1993). Naturalness, Intrinsicality, and Duplication. Ph.D. thesis University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Skyrms, B. (1983). Zeno’s Paradox of Measure. In R. S. Cohen & L. Laudan (Eds.), Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis: Essays in Honour of Adolf Grunbaum Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 223–254). Dordrecht: Springer.
Sterrett, S. G. (2009). Similarity and Dimensional Analysis. In A. Meijers (Ed.), Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences Handbook of the Philosophy of Science (pp. 799–823). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Suppes, P., Krantz, D., Luce, D., & Tversky, A. (1989). Foundations of Measurement, Vol. 2: Geometrical, Threshold, and Probabilistic Representations. San Diego: Academic Press.
Thomson, J. F. (1954). Tasks and Super-Tasks. Analysis, 15, 1–13.
Towster, E. (1975). Two Ugly Duckling Theorems for Concept-Formers. Information Sciences, 8, 359–368.
Tversky, A. (1977). Features of Similarity. Psychological Review, 84, 327–352.
Wang, Z., & Klir, G. J. (2009). Generalized Measure Theory. Number 25 in IFSR International Series on Systems Science and Engineering. New York: Springer.
Watanabe, S. (1965). Une Explication Mathématique Du Classement D’objets. In S. Dockx & P. Bernays (Eds.), Information and Prediction in Science. New York: Academic Press.
Watanabe, S. (1969). Knowing and Guessing. New York: Wiley.
Watanabe, S. (1985). Pattern Recognition: Human and Mechanical. New York: Wiley.
Weisberg, M. (2012). Getting Serious About Similarity. Philosophy of Science, 79, 785–794.
Williamson, T. (1988). First-Order Logics for Comparative Similarity. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 29, 457–481.
Yi, B.-U. (2018). Nominalism and Comparative Similarity. Erkenntnis, 83, 793–803.
Acknowledgements
Thanks to John Baez, Zach Barnett, Bob Beddor, Jens-Christian Bjerring, Antony Eagle, Jay Garfield, Jeremiah Joven Joaquin, David Kovacs, Dan Marshall, Neil Mehta, Qu Hsueh Ming, Daniel Nolan, Josh Parsons, Alexander Paseau, Michael Pelczar, Abelard Podgorski, Alex Sandgren, Kranti Saran, Nicholas Silins, Nick Smith, Neil Sinhababu and Weng Hong Tang, as well as audiences at the National Chung Cheng University, the University of Delhi, the University of Sydney and the Australasian Association of Philosophy conference at the University of Queensland in 2013 for discussion of this paper.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher’s Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Blumson, B. Does everything resemble everything else to the same degree?. AJPH 1, 22 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-022-00023-5
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-022-00023-5