Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Democracy Unchained: Contractualism, Individualism, and Independence in Buchanan’s Democratic Theory

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Homo Oeconomicus Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Contrary to the claims of some of his critics, James Buchanan was an ardent democrat. I argue that Buchanan’s conception of democratic governance organized by a contractually justified constitution is highly distinctive because of his commitment to a strong conception of individualism. For Buchanan, democracy is neither justified instrumentally—by the goods it generates—nor by reference to some antecedent conception of justice. Instead, democracy is the only political option for a society that takes individualism seriously. One implication of this view is that democracies can only be limited by the rules they collectively give themselves in the form of constitutions. I explicate this conception of democracy and address some of its implications, assumptions, and challenges.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout, following Southwood (2010), I use “contractualism” as a general catch-all term for any social contract theory.

  2. On the details of this “representation” condition for contractualism, see (Thrasher 2019a, b).

  3. A point that, as Holcombe notes (2018), puts Buchanan’s contractualism and his classical liberalism in potential tension. This feature of Buchanan’s thought should give more pause both to Buchanan’s followers as well as his critics.

  4. In an intriguing footnote, Buchanan (1977, 117, n. 6) argues that even Rawls’s A Theory of Justice can be interpreted as an “essay in persuasion,” an “attempt to convince readers that they should agree on” Rawls’s principles. Buchanan goes on to argue that we should not see Rawls as proffering a normative argument for the direct implementation of those principles.

  5. Frank Knight viewed these two things differently. “Persuasion”, for Knight, is the potentially coercive attempt to turn someone to your point of view, while “discussion” is an exchange of ideas unconstrained by strategy (Gordon 1974, 574). Notice the subtle path from Knights “democracy as discussion” where discussion is an exchange of ideas to Buchanan’s “politics of exchange”.

  6. William Riker never precisely defines “populism,” but his references to Rousseau and the general will make it clear that the core ideas of populism for Riker are (1) a positive conception of freedom bound up with collective choice and (2) and the result of democratic procedure should be taken as the true and good decision of the people as a whole. The radical implication—that Buchanan does not share—is that the result of collective choice should stand in as a right reason for the individual choosers. Buchanan does not claim that the democratic process acts as the true voice of public reason or that this reason should silence the individual reason of citizens.

  7. Contrast with William Riker in Liberalism Against Populism.

  8. Some have taken up this reductio affirmatively, the most sophisticated and ingenious is work by List and Pettit (2002, 2011).

  9. Individualism is “thin” is the sense that it neither assumes nor justifies much. It does, however, constrain options in important ways, which gives it its bite. Thanks to Chris Melenovsky for pushing me to clarify this point.

  10. There is a discussion of the “natural distribution” in the Limits of Liberty that is related to Winston Bush’s (1972) earlier model, but both are about the distribution of resources between parties not about how those parties are defined. Whether, for instance, one party could be the property (wholly or partially) of another is a question antecedent to the kind of model that Bush develops and Buchanan alludes to. Hobbes pretty clearly leaves it open that individuals can claim other people as their property and so I do not think this fundamental question should be excluded from contract theory.

  11. Perhaps of the sort that Thrasher (2019a) defend as a “personal sovereignty” conception of self-ownership. Regardless, this does suggest that Gaus’s (2018) point that prudential rational choice alone cannot generate Buchanan’s contractualism is well founded.

  12. This points back to the Frank Knight quote I started with. Thanks to Chris Melenovsky for pushing me to make this point explicit.

References

  • Achen, C. H., & Bartels, L. M. (2016). Democracy for realists: Why elections do not produce responsive government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1998). Game theory and the social contract, Vol. 2: Just playing. London: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, J. (2009). Polluting the polls: When citizens should not vote. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87(4), 535–549.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, J. (2016). Against democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. (1985). The reason of rules. The collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Kliemt, H. (2019). Private and political exchange—Nozick’s club vs. Buchanan’s communitarian contractarianism. In K. Marker, A. Schmitt, & J. Sirsch (Eds.), Demokratie und Entscheidung: Beiträge zur Analytischen Politischen Theorie (pp. 107–129). Wiesbaden: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-24529-0_8.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. (1997). Democracy and decision: The pure theory of electoral preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1954a). Social choice, democracy, and free markets. Journal of Political Economy, 62(2), 114–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1954b). Individual choice in voting and the market. Journal of Political Economy, 62(4), 334–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1962). Marginal notes on the reading of political philosophy. In J. Buchanan & G. Tullock (Eds.), The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. The collected works of James M. Buchanan (Vol. 3, pp. 305–325). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1967). Politics and science: Reflections on knight’s critique of polyani. The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. The collected works of James M. Buchanan (pp. 230–243). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1975). The limits of liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan. Vol. 7. The collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1977). The use and abuse of contract. Choice, contract, and constitutions. The collected works of James M. Buchanan (Vol. 16, pp. 111–123). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1986). Contractarianism and democracy. Choice, contract, and constitutions. The collected works of James M. Buchanan (Vol. 16, pp. 215–224). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. The collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bush, W. C. (1972). Individual Welfare in Anarchy. In G. Tullock (Ed.), Explorations in the theory of anarchy (pp. 5–18). Blacksburg: Center for the Study of Public Choice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2011). The myth of the rational voter: Why democracies choose bad policies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, D. (2008). Democratic authority: A philosophical framework. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (1983). The modern liberal theory of man. London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2001). Bosanquet’s communitarian defense of economic individualism: A lesson in the complexities of political theory. In A. Simhony & D. Weinstein (Eds.), The new liberalism: Reconciling liberty and community (pp. 137–158). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511558337.007.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2013). The turn to a political liberalism. In M. Jon & D. Reidy (Eds.), A companion to rawls (pp. 233–250). Oxford: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2018). It can’t be rational choice all the way down: Comprehensive hobbesianism and the origins of the moral order. In P. Boettke & S. Stein (Eds.), Buchanan’s tensions: Reexamining the political economy and philosophy of James M. Buchanan. Mercatus Center: Arlington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G., & Thrasher, J. (2015). Rational choice in the original position: The (many) models of Rawls and Harsanyi. In T. Hinton (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to the original position (pp. 39–58). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1986). Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1993). Uniting separate persons. In D. Gauthier & R. Sugden (Eds.), Rationality, Justice and the social contract: Themes from morals by agreement (pp. 176–192). Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (2013a). Achieving pareto-optimality: Invisible hands, social contracts, and rational deliberation. Rationality Markets and Morals, 4, 191–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (2013b). Twenty-five on. Ethics, 123(4), 601–624. https://doi.org/10.1086/670246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, S. (1974). Frank knight and the tradition of liberalism. Journal of Political Economy, 82(3), 571–577. https://doi.org/10.1086/260213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1651). Leviathan. In N. Malcolm (Ed.), Clarendon edition of the works of Thomas Hobbes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, R. G. (2018). Can consent limit liberty? Buchanan’s tensions: Rexamining the political economy and philosophy of James M. Buchanan (pp. 75–98). Mercatus Center: Arlington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (2011). Bukantianism—Buchanan's philosophical economics. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 80(2), 275–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. H. (1950). Economic and social policy in democratic society. Journal of Political Economy, 58(6), 513–522.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, H. (2012). Democratic reason: Politics, collective intelligence, and the rule of the many. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D., & Peart, S. (2018). Limits on the application of motivational homogeneity in the work of Buchanan and the Virginia School. In P. Boettke & S. Stein (Eds.), Buchanan’s tensions: Reexamining the political economy and philosophy of James M. Buchanan (pp. 171–191). Mercatus Center: Arlington.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2002). Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result. Economics and Philosophy, 18(1), 89–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2018). Minimal morality: A multilevel social contract theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R. (2017). Social contract theory for a diverse world: Beyond tolerance. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice. Harvard : Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. (1982). Liberalism against populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. Reissue: Waveland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Somin, I. (2016). Democracy and political ignorance: Why smaller government is smarter (2nd ed.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southwood, N. (2010). Contractualism and the foundations of morality. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2018). The community of advantage: A behavioural economist’s defence of the market. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thrasher, J. (2014). Uniqueness and symmetry in bargaining theories of justice. Philosophical Studies, 167(3), 683–699.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thrasher, J. (2019a). Self-ownership as personal sovereignty. Social Philosophy and Policy.

  • Thrasher, J. (2019b). Constructivism, representation, and stability: Path-dependence in public reason theories of justice. Synthese, 196(1), 429–450. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1488-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thrasher, J., & Gaus, G. (2017). On the calculus of consent. In J. Levy (Ed.), Oxford handbook on classics in political theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilfrid, S. (1963). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. Science, perception and reality. Atascadero: Ridgeview Pub Co.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Thrasher.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thrasher, J. Democracy Unchained: Contractualism, Individualism, and Independence in Buchanan’s Democratic Theory. Homo Oecon 36, 25–40 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s41412-019-00085-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s41412-019-00085-6

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation