Skip to main content

Objective and Subjective Consequentialism Reconsidered

Abstract

The objective of the paper is to explicate and critically appreciate two forms of consequentialism, namely objective and subjective consequentialism. Consequentialism is a substantive moral theory according to which moral value or good is to produce/promote best consequences (in a sense welfare); and morally right consists in acting so as to promote maximum good (in case of utilitarianism) or to promote best or most good. However, the paper considers important questions, replies to which give us two forms of consequentialism, namely subjective and objective consequentialism, each having their unique features, nuances and limits. Moot problems are as follows: Whether consequentialism as a theory of good is to promote actual good, that is good as matter-of-fact or expected good, that is good expected by the moral agent; and whether as a theory of right, it urges to make decisions for the promotion of good based on some heuristic devices or subjective motives, commitments and so on. Objective consequentialism, as a theory of good prefers promotion of actual good than expected good, and as a theory of right decision-making urges the moral agents to rely on heuristic devices than subjective factors. The contest has been absorbing and fierce, each having so-called strong arguments. The paper reconsiders these contesting arguments and critically examines those to conclude in favour of objective consequentialism on important counts notwithstanding, the value of motives, motivations and commitments of moral agents.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Notes

  1. Two senses in which ‘right’ should be understood has been well explained by Alan Gibbard in Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgment and Derek Parfit in On what matters I.

  2. An action has a higher deontic value than an alternative course of action when performance of that action of necessity has higher probability to promote greater good or value (which is, best consequences).

  3. The concept of ‘expected goodness’ of acts has been discussed by Julia Driver in Uneasy Virtue; also by Michael Slote in From Morality to Virtue & in Fred Feldman’s paper: actual utility, the objections of impracticality and the move to expected utility.

  4. The term expectabilism has been used and discussed by Julia Driver in Consequentialism and Michael Slote in From morality to virtue. The term foreseeabilism has been  used and discussed by Derek Parfit in What matters I & in Nikil Mukerji’s work: The Case Against Consequentialism Reconsidered.

  5. Heuristic devices are some such moral rules, much like secondary rules of morality, following which enables promotion of best consequences.

References

  • Bazerman, M. H., & Tenbrunsel, A. E. (2011). Blind Spots: Why we fail to do what is right to do about it. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cooking, D., & Oakley, J. (1995). Indirect consequentialism, friendship and the problem of alienation. Ethics, 106(1), 86–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2012). Consequentialism. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver,. (2003). Uneasy virtue. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (1997a). On the intrinsic value of pleasures. Utilitarianism, hedonism and desert (pp. 125–147). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (1997b). World utilitarianism. Utilitarianism, hedonism and desert (pp. 17–35). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fred, F. (2006). Actual Utility, the objections of impracticality and the move to expected utility. Philosophical Studies., 129(1), 49–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgment. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2008). Moral intuition-fast and frugal heuristic? In W. Sinnot-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (vol. 2): The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 1–26). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. H. (2003). Practical rules: When we need them and when we don’t. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (2003). A rule-consequentialist theory of morality (p. 142). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, P. (2006). Does consequentialism make too many demands or none at all? Ethics, 116, 680–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, P. (1991). Decision-theoretic consequentialism and the nearest and dearest objection. Ethics, 101, 465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, E. (1998). Can indirect consequentialist be a real friend? Ethics, 108, 386–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mukerji, N. (2016). The case against consiquentialism reconsidered. Switzerland: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mulgan, T. (2001). The demands of Consequentialism. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). Moral luck. Mortal questions (pp. 24–38). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (1990). Consequentialism and the unforeseeable future. Analysis, 50, 253–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters I. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P., & Brennan, G. (1986). Restrictive consequentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64(4), 438–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1984). Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs., 13(2), 134–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnot-Armstrong, W. (Ed.). (2008). Moral psychology (vol. 2): The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (1995). From morality to virtue. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, M. (2002). Moral theory: An introduction. Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I acknowledge the academic services of Dr. Komal Kushwaha in typing, formatting and finalizing the paper in its present form.

Funding

No funds, grants or other support were received.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Debashis Guha.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose, and the author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article. I have no conflict of interest regarding my paper ‘Objective and Subjective Consequentialism Reconsidered’ submitted to the JICPR.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Guha, D. Objective and Subjective Consequentialism Reconsidered. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 40, 115–131 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-023-00299-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-023-00299-9

Keyword