Skip to main content
Log in

The myth of Frederic Clements’s mutualistic organicism, or: on the necessity to distinguish different concepts of organicism

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the theory and history of ecology, Frederic Clements’s theory of plant communities is usually presented as the historical prototype and a paradigmatic example of synecological organicism, characterised by the assumption that ecological communities are functionally integrated units of mutually dependent species. In this paper, I will object to this standard interpretation of Clements’s theory. Undoubtedly, Clements compares plant communities with organisms and calls them “complex organisms” and “superorganisms”. Further, he can indeed be regarded as a proponent of ecological organicism—provided that one defines ecological organicism as the interpretation of synecological units according to the model of the individual organism. However, Clements’s theory does not include the assumption that mutual dependence is a principle of the organisation of plant communities. Rather, he interprets plant communities as top-down control-hierarchical entities, in which subordinate species depend on dominant species—but not the other way around. Therefore, his theory represents what may be called ‘control-hierarchical organicism’ as against ‘mutualistic organicism’. The erroneous attribution to Clements of ‘mutualistic organicism’ might be due to an unawareness of the existence of different concepts of the organism. This unawareness results in the projection on Clements’s theory of a seemingly self-evident mutualistic concept of organism that Clements himself did not use as a basis for his theory of plant communities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Eliot’s (2007, 2011) diachronic interpretations are insightful and appropriate in many ways. However, he seems not to take sufficient account of the fact that Clements (but not Gleason) imagined an—admittedly ideal—state of self-stabilization in which the reactions of a plant community upon its habitat become “stabilizing or climatic” causes (which counteract further changes) as opposed to “continuing or ecesic” causes (which drive succession forward) (Clements 1916: 5; cf. ibid.: 55, 98, 350 f.). That is, Eliot does not sufficiently acknowledge that Clements’s theory includes the developmental concept of perfection, i.e. of a finite process leading towards a certain predetermined ideal state or goal, while Gleason’s theory refers to the developmental concept of incessant change, i.e. of an infinite process leading permanently away from the current state but never towards a certain ideal state (see Kirchhoff 2014b for a characterisation of these concepts).

  2. Nevertheless, Eliot (2011: 75) develops convincing arguments against the false assertation that Clements assumes a mutualistic organisation of plant communities that exhibits the same degree of specialization and interdependence among its component species as the organs of animals or even much simpler organisms such as paramecia. However, in contrast to my own position, Eliot does not completely rule out ascribing a doctrine of mutualistic organisation to Clements—as long as it does not ascribe species-specific interdependencies but allows for intersubstitutability of functionally equivalent species (ibid.). Accordingly, contrary to my interpretation, Eliot claims that Clements’s “comparison [of plant communities] to [individual] organisms encompasses [… the view that] their component parts demonstrate interdependence acquired through historical adaptation or accommodation to one another” (ibid.: 72 f.), and concludes that “the organism comparison implies a degree of functional integration, even if it is loose” (ibid.: 76).

  3. In this paper, I use the expressions “mutual dependence” and interdependence” as synonyms that both mean (direct or indirect) “reciprocal dependence” as opposed to “one-sided dependence”.

  4. Emphasis of “superorganism” omitted.

  5. Worster does not cite the source of this quotation. It might stem from Spencer (1860), although, given this, the correct quotation would be without “or injure”. I quote the whole passage from Spencer to make more evident his analogy between human societies or communities and single organisms: “Simple communities, like simple creatures, have so little mutual dependence of parts, that mutilation or subdivision causes but little inconvenience; but from complex communities, as from complex creatures, you cannot remove any considerable organ without producing great disturbance or death of the rest.”

  6. Worster does not cite the source of this quotation either, and the same applies to his next quotation from Spencer.

  7. Emphasis of “Clementsian community” omitted.

  8. My analysis includes the following publications: Clements (1905, 1907, 1916, 1935a, b, 1936), Clements et al. (1929), Weaver and Clements (1938), Clements and Shelford (1939).

  9. “Clements’ formations were, in effect, physiognomic units” (Nicolson 1989: 144; cf. Kirchhoff 2007: 185 f.).

  10. As Clements regards competition as constitutive of ecological communities (Clements et al. 1929: 327), he does not count pioneer stages of vegetation among communities because they do not exhibit competition.

  11. Emphasis of “Subdominants” omitted.

  12. I will not further discuss this difference because it is irrelevant as regards my critique of the synchronic standard interpretation of Clements’s theory.

  13. For a conceptual distinction between “dependence” and “mutual dependence” or “interdependence” as well as the possibly “facultative” or “obligate”, “beneficial” or “necessary beneficial”, “direct” or “indirect”, “oligophilic” or “polyphilic” character of these ecological relations (see Boucher et al. 1982; Kirchhoff 2007; Eliot 2018).

  14. In nested hierarchies, the elements of the higher level consist of the elements of the lower level, e.g. organisms of organs and organs of cells. In non-nested hierarchies this is not the case, e.g. generals do not consist of (but control) their lieutenants, who do not consist of (but control) their sergeants, and so on. For this distinction between nested and non-nested hierarchies (see Allen and Starr 1982). For the classification of control hierarchies as non-nested hierarchies (cf. Keller and Golley 2000a: 30).

  15. This reference to Hagen is based on a hint by Antoine C. Dussault.

  16. See Sect. 1 for Hagen’s and Eliot’s critique of this ascription.

  17. Clements et al. erroneously indicate “94”.

  18. Some of Warming’s statements, however, indicate an individualistic concept of plant communities rather than an organismic one. For example, he states directly before the passage cited above: “The plant-community […] is merely a congregation of units among which there is no co-operation for the common weal but rather a ceaseless struggle of all against all” (Warming and Vahl 1909: 95). These at first view apparently contradictory statements might be compatible if one assumes that Warming’s first statement does not represent a theory of mutual dependence of properties and of mutual dependence for survival (mutualistic organicism) but a theory of mutual dependence of properties only (holistic individualism; cf. Pettit 1993). For a more detailed discussion of Warming’s theory (see Anker 2011; besides Goodland 1975; Acot 1995).

  19. For a more detailed discussion of Thienemann’s theory (see Golley 1993: 38–41, 56; Potthast 2001; Kirchhoff 2007: 205–214; Kirchhoff and Voigt 2010: 185; Schwarz and Jax 2011).

  20. I refer to the third edition (1971) of the “Fundamentals of Ecology” which was published by Eugene P. Odum alone, while the first (1953) and second (1959) edition were published by E. P. Odum in collaboration with his brother Howard T. Odum.

  21. An encaptic hierarchy is a hierarchy in which the higher level is composed of the lower level. In the case of Odum, organs are composed of cells, organisms of organs, populations of organisms, and so forth.

  22. For a more detailed discussion of Odum’s theory (see Golley 1991; Bergandi 1995; Kirchhoff 2007: 214–233; Voigt 2009; Kirchhoff and Voigt 2010: 190 f.).

  23. See https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/organism, accessed 2019-01-22.

  24. My translation. The German-language original reads as follows: “Als das zentrale Moment, das Organismen als eine Einheit mit einem speziellen ontologischen und methodologischen Status kennzeichnet, gilt seit Mitte des 18. Jahrhunderts die Wechselseitigkeit” (Toepfer 2011: 790).

  25. My translation. The German-language original reads as follows: “Ein Organismus ist ein materielles System aus wechselseitig voneinander abhängigen Teilen und Prozessen, das in physischer und funktionaler Hinsicht eine integrierte Einheit bildet und charakteristische Funktionen und Aktivitäten (wie Ernährung, Schutz vor Störungen und Rezeption von Umweltereignissen) aufweist. […] Die physische Einheit eines Organismus besteht in seiner materiellen Verfasstheit in einem kontinuierlich bestehenden kohärenten Körper, dessen Stoffe und Form jedoch einem Wechsel unterliegen können (durch Metabolismus und Metamorphose). Die funktionale Einheit des Systems besteht in seiner Organisation, d.h. in einem Gefüge aus Prozessen, die seine materiellen Teile erzeugen und erhalten und die damit (als Prozesse eines jeweiligen Typs) wechselseitig voneinander abhängen” (Toepfer 2011: 777).

  26. As regards the emergence of this concept of organism in the theories of, especially, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Immanuel Kant and Georges Cuvier (see Cheung 2000; 2010; Kirchhoff 2002; Weil 2005; Kirchhoff 2007; Toepfer 2011). For the influence of Kant’s mutualistic organicism on biologists (see, e.g., Gilbert and Sarkar 2000: 3).

  27. For a description and justification of the approach to link ecological theories with sociological theories (see, e.g., Ghiselin 1969; Schweber 1977, 1980; Nicolson 1989; Trepl 1994; Kirchhoff and Trepl 2001; Eisel 2004; 2009; Allen 2005; Kirchhoff 2007; Voigt 2009; Kirchhoff 2014a/b).

  28. For a discussion of different concepts of “organism” and “organicism” (see, e.g., Alverdes 1936; Needham 1928; Phillips 1970; Gloy 1996; Gilbert and Sarkar 2000; Rehmann-Sutter 2000; Allen 2005; Toepfer 2011; Wolfe 2014).

References

  • Acot, P. (1995). L’ecologie a cent ans: Hommage a Eugenius Warming. Ecologie,26(1), 5–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. E. (2005). Mechanism, vitalism and organicism in late nineteenth and twentieth-century biology: The importance of historical context. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part C,36(2), 261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, T. F. H. & Starr, T. B. (1982). Hierarchy. Perspectives for ecological complexity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alverdes, F. (1936). Organizismus und Holismus. Neuere theoretische Strömungen in der Biologie. Der Biologe,5(4), 121–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, D. J. & Kikkawa, J. (1986). Development of concepts. In J. Kikkawa & D. J. Anderson (Eds.), Community ecology: Pattern and process (pp. 3–16). Melbourne: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anker, P. (2011). Plant community, Plantesamfund. In A. Schwarz & K. Jax (Eds.), Ecology revisited. Reflecting on concepts, advancing science (pp. 325–331). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, C. I. (2003). Romantic organicism. From idealist origins to ambivalent afterlife. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, M. G. (1996). Ecological fragmentation in the fifties. In W. Cronon (Ed.), Uncommon ground: Rethinking the human place in nature (pp. 233–255). New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, M. G., Burk, J. H. & Pitts, W. D. (1987). Terrestrial plant ecology (2nd ed.). San Francisco: Benjamin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, M. G., Burk, J. H., Pitts, W. D., Gilliam, F. S. & Schwartz, M. W. (1999). Terrestrial Plant Ecology (3rd ed.). Menlo Park: Addison Wesley Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begon, M., Harper, J. L. & Townsend, C. R. (1986). Ecology. Individuals, populations and communities. Boston: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begon, M., Harper, J. L., & Townsend, C. R. (1990). Ecology. Individuals, populations and communities. Boston: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begon, M., Townsend, C. R. & Harper, J. L. (2006). Ecology. From individuals to ecosystems (4th ed.). Malden/MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergandi, D. (1995). ‘Reductionist Holism’: an oxymoron or a philosophical chimaera of EP Odum’s systems ecology? Ludus vitalis,3(5), 145–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergthaller, H. (2004). Ökologie zwischen Wissenschaft und Weltanschauung. Untersuchungen zur Literatur der modernen amerikanischen Umweltbewegung: Aldo Leopold, Rachel Carson, Gary Snyder und Edward Abbey. Bonn: Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität zu Bonn.

  • Boucher, D. H. (1985). The idea of mutualism, past and future. In D. H. Boucher (Ed.), The biology of mutualism: Ecology and evolution (pp. 1–28). Beckenham: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boucher, D. H., James, S. & Keeler, K. H. (1982). The ecology of mutualism. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 13, 315–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burwick, F. (1987). Introduction. In F. Burwick (Ed.), Approaches to Organic Form Permutations in Science and Culture (pp. 9–14). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Buzan, B. & Albert, M. (2010). Differentiation: A sociological approach to international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations,16(3), 315–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherif, A. H. (1990). Mutualism: The forgotten concept in teaching science. The American Biology Teacher,52(4), 206–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheung, T. (2000). Die Organisation des Lebendigen. Die Entstehung des biologischen Organismusbegriffs bei Cuvier, Leibniz und Kant. Frankfurt/M.: Campus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheung, T. (2010). What is an ‘organism’? On the occurrence of a new term and its conceptual transformations 1680–1850. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences,32(2–3), 155–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, N. L. (2014). An historical perspective on forest succession and its relevance to ecosystem restoration and conservation practice in North America. Forest Ecology and Management,330, 312–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1905). Research methods in ecology. Lincoln: The University Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1907). Plant physiology and ecology. New York: Holt.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1916). Plant succession. An analysis of the development of vegetation. Washington: Carnegie Institution of Washington.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1920). Plant indicators. The relation of plant communities to process and practice. Washington: Carnegie Institution of Washington.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1935a). Experimental ecology in the public service. Ecology,16(3), 342–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1935b). Plant succession and human problems. In B. W. Allred & E. S. Clements (Eds.), Dynamics of Vegetation. Selections from the writings of Frederic E. Clements (pp. 1–21). New York: Wilson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1936). Nature and structure of the climax. The Journal of Ecology,24(1), 252–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E., & Shelford, V. E. (1939). Bio-Ecology. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E., Weaver, J. E. & Hanson, H. C. (1929). Plant competition. An analysis of community functions. Washington: Carnegie Institution of Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, W. S. (1926). The fundamentals of vegetational change. Ecology,7(4), 391–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dussault, A. C. (2020). Neither superorganisms nor mere species aggregates: Charles Elton’s sociological analogies and his moderate holism about ecological communities. History and Philosophy of Life Sciences [accepted for publication].

  • Eisel, U. (2004). Politische Schubladen als theoretische Heuristik. Methodische Aspekte politischer Bedeutungs-verschiebungen in Naturbildern. In L. Fischer (Ed.), Projektionsfläche Natur. Zum Zusammenhang von Naturbildern und gesellschaftlichen Verhältnissen (pp. 29–43). Hamburg: Hamburg University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisel, U. (2009). Orte als Individuen. Zur Rekonstruktion eines spatial turn in der Soziologie. In U. Eisel (Ed.), Landschaft und Gesellschaft. Räumliches Denken im Visier (pp. 226–279). Münster: Westfälisches Dampfboot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eliot, C. (2007). Method and metaphysics in Clements’s and Gleason’s ecological explanations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,38(1), 85–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliot, C. (2011). The legend of order and chaos: communities and early community ecology. In K. de Laplante, B. Brown, & K. A. Peacock (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science. Volume 11: Philosophy of ecology (pp. 49–107). North Holland: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eliot, C. (2018). Ecological interdependence via constraints. Philosophy of Science,85(5), 1115–1126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elwick, J. (2003). Herbert Spencer and the disunity of the social organism. History of Science,41(1), 35–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. & Brooks, D. S. (2018). Levels of organization in biology. In: E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu: Stanford University, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/levels-org-biology/.

  • Esposito, M. (2016). Romantic biology, 1890–1945. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma, D. J. & Moreno, G. (1988). The evolution of ecological specialization. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics,19(1), 207–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerard, R. W. (1969). Hierarchy, entitation, and levels. In L. L. Whyte, A. G. Wilson & D. Wilson (Eds.), Hierarchical structures (pp. 215–228). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1969). The Triumph of the Darwinian method. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, A. H. (2017). The path to the present. In M. Ruse & R. J. Richards (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of evolutionary ethics (pp. 72–86). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F. & Sarkar, S. (2000). Embracing complexity: Organicism for the 21st century. Developmental Dynamics,219, 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gloy, K. (1996). Das Verständnis der Natur. Band 2: Die Geschichte des ganzheitlichen Denkens. München: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golley, F. B. (1991). The ecosystem concept: A search for order. Ecological Research,6(2), 129–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golley, F. B. (1993). A history of the ecosystem concept in ecology more than the sum of the parts. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodland, R. J. (1975). The Tropical Origin of Ecology: Eugen Warming’s Jubilee. Oikos,26(2), 240–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagen, J. B. (1988). Organism and environment: Frederic Clements’s vision of a unified physiological ecology. In R. Rainger, K. R. Benson & J. Maienschein (Eds.), The American development of biology (pp. 257–277). Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagen, J. B. (1992). An Entangled Bank. The origins of ecosystem ecology. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagen, J. B. (1993). Clementsian ecologists: The internal dynamics of a research school. Osiris,8, 178–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hard, G. (1994). Die Natur, die Stadt und die Ökologie. Reflexionen über ‘Stadtnatur’ und ‘Stadtökologie’. In H. Ernste (Ed.), Pathways to Human Ecology (pp. 161–180). Bern: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, H. S. (1976). Succession. In R. M. May (Ed.), Theoretical ecology. Principles and applications (pp. 187–204). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. & Wolfe, C. T. (2010). The Concept of Organism: Historical, philosophical, scientific perspectives. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences,32(2–3), 145–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, G. E. (1958). Concluding remarks. Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology,22, 415–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jax, K. (2002). Die Einheiten der Ökologie. Analyse, Methodenentwicklung und Anwendung in Ökologie und Naturschutz. Frankfurt/M.: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jax, K. (2006). Ecological units: Definitions and application. The Quarterly Review of Biology,81(3), 237–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Journet, D. (1991). Ecological theories as cultural narratives: F. E. Clements’s and H. A. Gleason’s ‘stories’ of community succession. Written Communication,8(4), 446–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790/1987): Critique of judgment. Including the First introduction. Translated, with an Introduction, by Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett.

  • Keller, D. & Golley, F. B. (2000a). Entities and process in ecology. In D. Keller & F. B. Golley (Eds.), The philosophy of ecology. From science to synthesis (pp. 21–33). Athens: The University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, D. & Golley, F. B. (2000b). Reductionism and holism. In D. Keller & F. B. Golley (Eds.), The philosophy of ecology. From science to synthesis (pp. 171–179). Athens: The University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingsland, S. E. (2005). The evolution of american ecology, 1890–2000. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, T. (2002). Der Organismus—zur’metaphysischen Konstitution’ eines empirischen Gegenstandes. In A. Lotz & J. Gnädinger (Eds.), Wie kommt die Ökologie zu ihren Gegenständen? Gegenstandskonstitution und Modellierung in den ökologischen Wissenschaften (pp. 153–179). Frankfurt/M.: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, T. (2006). Systemauffassungen und biologische Theorien. Zur Herkunft von Individualitätskonzeptionen und ihrer Bedeutung für die Theoriebildung in der Ökologie. München: Dissertation, Technische Universität München.

  • Kirchhoff, T. (2007). Systemauffassungen und biologische Theorien. Zur Herkunft von Individualitätskonzeptionen und ihrer Bedeutung für die Theorie ökologischer Einheiten. [Systems approaches and biological theories. On the origins of concepts of individuality and their significance for the theory of ecological units]. Freising: Technische Universität München. Also available online: https://mediatum.ub.tum.de/685961.

  • Kirchhoff, T. (2013). Hidden values in competing concepts of community-level biodiversity. In J. Friedrich, A. Halsband & L. Minkmar (Eds.), Biodiversity and society. Societal dimensions of the conservation and utilization of biological diversity (pp. 75–89). Göttingen: Universitätsverlag Göttingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, T. (2014a). Community-level biodiversity: an inquiry into the ecological and cultural background and practical consequences of opposing concepts. In D. Lanzerath & M. Friele (Eds.), Concepts and values in biodiversity (pp. 99–119). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, T. (2014b). Die Zeitform der Entwicklung von Ökosystemen und ökologischen Gesellschaften. Richtschnur für menschliche Vergesellschaftung? In G. Hartung (Ed.), Mensch und Zeit. Synchronisation der Zeit als Grundproblem der interdisziplinären Anthropologie (pp. 226–248). Berlin: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, T. (2018). ‘Kulturelle Ökosystemdienstleistungen’. Eine begriffliche und methodische Kritik. [‘Cultural Ecosystem Services’. A Conceptual and Methodological Critique]. Freiburg: Alber.

  • Kirchhoff, T. & Trepl, L. (2001). Vom Wert der Biodiversität. Über konkurrierende politische Theorien in der Diskussion um Biodiversität. Zeitschrift für angewandte Umweltforschung,S13, 27–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, T. & Voigt, A. (2010). Rekonstruktion der Geschichte der Synökologie. Konkurrierende Paradigmen, Transformationen, kulturelle Hintergründe. Verhandlungen zur Geschichte und Theorie der Biologie,15, 181–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krohs, U. & Toepfer, G. (Eds.). (2005). Philosophie der Biologie. Eine Einführung. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt/M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1968). Evolution in changing environment. Some theoretical explorations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (1997/2013). Theory of society (Vol. 2). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Luzuriaga, A. L., Sánchez, A. M., Maestre, F. T. & Escudero, A. (2012). Assemblage of a semi-arid annual plant community: Abiotic and biotic filters act hierarchically. PLoS ONE,7(7), e41270–e41270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur, R. H. & Levins, R. (1967). The limiting similarity, convergence and divergence of coexisting species. American Naturalist,101(921), 377–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, J. & Sterelny, K. (2008). What is biodiversity?. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, A. (1998). A postmodern natural history of the world: eviscerating the GUTs from ecology and environmentalism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,29(1), 137–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGregor, R. K. (2018). The Story of a Forest: Growth, Destruction and Renewal in the Upper Delaware Valley. Jefferson: McFarland.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. P. (1985). The background of ecology: Concept and theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. (2001). What functions explain. Functional explanation and self-reproducing systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, F. (1992). Hierarchical approaches to ecosystem theory. Ecological Modelling,63(1), 215–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Needham, J. (1928). Organicism in biology. Journal of Philosophical Studies,3, 29–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolson, M. (1989). National styles, divergent classifications: A comparative case study from the history of French and American plant ecology. In L. Hargens, R. A. Jones & A. R. Pickering (Eds.), Knowledge and society. Studies in the sociology of science past and present. A research annual (pp. 139–186). Greenwich: JAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, R. V., DeAngelis, D. L., Waide, J. B. & Allen, T. F. H. (1986). A hierarchical concept of ecosystems. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2006). Ecology. In S. Sarkar & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), The Philosophy of science. An encyclopedia (Vol. 1, pp. 215–224). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2007). Seeing the forest and the trees: On the very idea of an ecological community. Philosophy of Science,74(5), 628–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odum, E. P. (1971). Fundamentals of ecology. Philadelphia: Saunders.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pepper, J. W. & Herron, M. D. (2008). Does biology need an organism concept? Biological Reviews,83(4), 621–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1993). The common mind. An essay on psychology, society and politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. C. (1970). Organicism in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Journal of the History of Ideas,31(3), 413–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potthast, T. (2001). Gefährliche Ganzheitsbetrachtung oder geeinte Wissenschaft von Leben und Umwelt? Epistemisch-moralische Hybride in der deutschen Ökologie 1925–1955. Verhandlungen zur Geschichte und Theorie der Biologie,7, 91–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehmann-Sutter, C. (2000). Biological organicism and the ethics of the human–nature relationship. Theory in Biosciences,119, 334–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, J. L. (1980). The organismic community: Resilience of an embattled ecological concept. BioScience,30(7), 465–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, J. (2009). Is there a general theory of community ecology? Biology and Philosophy,24(4), 521–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, A. & Jax, K. (2011). Early ecology in the German-speaking world through WWII. In A. Schwarz & K. Jax (Eds.), Ecology revisited. Reflecting on concepts, advancing science (pp. 231–275). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schweber, S. S. (1977). The origin of the Origin revisited. Journal of the History of Biology,10(2), 229–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweber, S. S. (1980). Darwin and the political economists: divergence of character. Journal of the History of Biology,13(2), 195–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, W. M. (1960). Herbert spencer and the ‘Social Organism’. Journal of the History of Ideas,21(2), 294–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southwood, T. R. E. (1987). The concept and nature of the community. In J. H. R. Gee & P. S. Giller (Eds.), Organization of communities: Past and present (pp. 3–27). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. (1860). The social organism. The Westminster Review,73, 90–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. (1898). Principles of sociology. In Three volumes (3rd ed.). New York: Appleton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tansley, A. G. (1922). The New Psychology and Its Relation to Life (Revised ed.). London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thienemann, A. F. (1939). Grundzüge einer allgemeinen Ökologie. Archiv für Hydrobiologie,35, 267–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thienemann, A. F. (1941). Leben und Umwelt. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thienemann, A. F. (1944). Der Mensch als Glied und Gestalter der Natur. Jena: Gronau.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thienemann, A. F. (1956). Leben und Umwelt. Vom Gesamthaushalt der Natur. Hamburg: Rowohlt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobey, R. C. (1981). Saving the prairies. The life cycle of the founding school of American Plant Ecology, 1895–1955. Berkeley: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toepfer, G. (2011). Organismus zsfdsf sdffs. In G. Toepfer (Ed.), Historisches Wörterbuch der Biologie. Geschichte und Theorie der biologischen Grundbegriffe, Band 2 (pp. 777–842). Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Trepl, L. (1987). Geschichte der Ökologie. Vom 17. Jahrhundert bis zur Gegenwart. Frankfurt/M.: Athenäum.

  • Trepl, L. (1994). Competition and coexistence: On the historical background in ecology and the influence of economy and social sciences. Ecological Modelling,75–76, 99–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trepl, L. (2005). Allgemeine Ökologie, Band 1 Organismus und Umwelt. Frankfurt/M.: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trepl, L. & Voigt, A. (2011). The classical holism-reductionism debate in ecology. In A. Schwarz & K. Jax (Eds.), Ecology revisited. Reflecting on concepts, advancing science (pp. 45–83). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tyrell, H. (2008a). Anfragen an die Theorie der gesellschaftlichen Differenzierung. In B. Heintz, A. Kieserling, S. Nacke, & R. Unkelbach (Eds.), Soziale und gesellschaftliche Differenzierung. Aufsätze zur soziologischen Theorie (pp. 75–105). Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyrell, H. (2008b). Zweierlei Differenzierung: Funktionale und Ebenendifferenzierung im Frühwerk Niklas Luhmanns. In B. Heintz, A. Kieserling, S. Nacke, & R. Unkelbach (Eds.), Soziale und gesellschaftliche Differenzierung. Aufsätze zur soziologischen Theorie (pp. 55–72). Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Baalen, M. & Huneman, P. (2014). Organisms as ecosystems/ecosystems as organisms. Biological Theory,9(4), 357–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vellend, M. (2012). The community concept. In Oxford University Press (Ed.), Oxford bibliographies online. http://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780199830060/obo-9780199830060-0011.xml. Oxford University Press.

  • Vellend, M. (2016). The theory of ecological communities. Princeton/NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voigt, A. (2009). Die Konstruktion der Natur. Ökologische Theorien und politische Philosophien der Vergesellschaftung. Stuttgart: Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warming, E. (1895). Plantesamfund—Grundtræk af den økologiske Plantegeografi. Kjøbenhavn: Philipsen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warming, E. & Vahl, M. (1909). Oecology of Plants. An Introduction to the Study of Plant-Communities [Extended and translated edition of Warming 1895]. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Weaver, J. E. & Clements, F. E. (1929). Plant ecology. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weaver, J. E. & Clements, F. E. (1938). Plant ecology (2nd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weil, A. (2005). Das Modell “Organismus” in der Ökologie. Möglichkeiten und Grenzen der Beschreibung synökologischer Einheiten [The Model “Organism” in Ecology. Possibilities and Limits of the Description of Synecological Units]. Frankfurt/M.: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, W. M. (1923). Social life among the insects. The Scientific Monthly,16(1), 5–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, C. T. (2014). The organism as ontological go-between: Hybridity, boundaries and degrees of reality in its conceptual history. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,48, 151–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worster, D. (1990). The ecology of order and chaos. Environmental History Review,14(1/2), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worster, D. (1994). Nature’s economy. A history of ecological ideas (2nd ed.). Cambridge/UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zylstra, U. (1992). Living things as hierarchically organized structures. Synthese,91, 111–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I dedicate this paper to the memory of Ludwig Trepl, in gratitude for his dedicated teaching and for the thorough and joyful discussions of topics like that of this paper which he made possible in his time as Chair of Landscape Ecology at the Technical University of Munich. I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers and the guest editors for their detailed comments that helped me to significantly improve the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Kirchhoff.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kirchhoff, T. The myth of Frederic Clements’s mutualistic organicism, or: on the necessity to distinguish different concepts of organicism. HPLS 42, 24 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00317-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00317-y

Keywords

Navigation