Skip to main content
Log in

What good are abstract and what-if models? Lessons from the Gaïa hypothesis

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article on the epistemology of computational models stems from an analysis of the Gaïa hypothesis (GH). It begins with James Kirchner’s criticisms of the central computational model of GH: Daisyworld. Among other things, the model has been criticized for being too abstract, describing fictional entities (fictive daisies on an imaginary planet) and trying to answer counterfactual (what-if) questions (how would a planet look like if life had no influence on it?). For these reasons the model has been considered not testable and therefore not legitimate in science, and in any case not very interesting since it explores non actual issues. This criticism implicitly assumes that science should only be involved in the making of models that are “actual” (by opposition to what-if) and “specific” (by opposition to abstract). I challenge both of these criticisms in this article. First by showing that although the testability—understood as the comparison of model output with empirical data—is an important procedure for explanatory models, there are plenty of models that are not testable. The fact that these are not testable (in this restricted sense) has nothing to do with their being “abstract” or “what-if” but with their being predictive models. Secondly, I argue that “abstract” and “what-if” models aim at (respectable) epistemic purposes distinct from those pursued by “actual and specific models”. Abstract models are used to propose how-possibly explanation or to pursue theorizing. What-if models are used to attribute causal or explanatory power to a variable of interest. The fact that they aim at different epistemic goals entails that it may not be accurate to consider the choice between different kinds of model as a “strategy“.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Notes

  1. For reviews, see Wood et al. (2008), McDonald-Gibson et al. (2008), Lenton and Williams (2009), Dutreuil (2013).

  2. Sarkar and Plutynski’s judgement of GH as being a “philosophically intriguing idea at the fringe of science” (2010, p. xxiii, my emphasis) belongs to the more sympathetic positions within the community. According to Ruse (2013, chap. 8), part of the reasons for the rejection of GH by evolutionary biologists, besides epistemological issues, are to be found in the own insecurity and tension that existed within evolutionary biology at the time GH was proposed.

  3. On GH and niche construction, see Free and Barton (2007), Pocheville (2010).

  4. For a detailed review, precise quotations, references and pages, see Dutreuil (2013).

  5. Kirchner also worries about the simplicity of Daisyworld which may not reflect the complexity of the world; for a discussion of this point, see Dyke and Weaver (2013), Dutreuil (2013).

  6. For details about “fidelity criteria” and “intended scope”, see Weisberg (2013), Sect. 3.3.

  7. One may worry that it may not be warranted to talk about one model and to talk about the same model (run in two different scenarios) since not only the values of some parameters may be modified but also the structure of the model. First, the modification of the structure that takes place here can actually be thought of as a borderline case of the change of the value of some parameters (bringing one parameter to zero). Second, calling model-A and model-B the two different scenarios does not change my argument, namely the idea that the comparison between the two (models or scenarios) is a particular modelling practice, which, as it will be argued below, is epistemologically sound and has a praticular epistemic purpose.

  8. Notice that the same algorithm may alternatively be used to explain or to predict phenomena depending on the epistemic context in which it is used. Besides, I would be happy to grant that there are grey cases where it is not clear in which epistemic situation (prediction or explanation) we are.

  9. Notice that one may rely on the source procedure even if one knows that part of the simulation artificially misrepresents the target but one has other reasons to believe in the validity of this model building technique (Winsberg 2006; Grüne-Yanoff and Weirich 2010).

  10. Huneman, this issue, offers a detailed and interesting discussion of the way the evaluation of the likelihood can be carried out.

References

  • Barberousse, A., & Vorms, M. (2013). Computer simulations and empirical data. In J. M. Durán & E. Arnold (Eds.), Computer simulations and the changing face of scientific experimentation (pp. 29–45). Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. A. (1999). “Can unrealistic computer models illuminate theoretical biology”. In A. S. Wu (Ed.), Proceedings of the 1999 genetic and evolutionary computation conference workshop program, (pp. 20–23). Orlando, FL, July 13.

  • Bedau, M. (2007). Artificial Life. In W. Gabbay, P. Thagard, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science, philosophy of biology (Vol. 3, pp. 595–613). Elsevier: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, R., Lenton, T., & Watson, A. (2011). Symbiotic physiology promotes homeostasis in Daisyworld. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 274(1), 170–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caldeira, K., & Kasting, J. (1992). The life span of the biosphere revisited. Nature, 360(6406), 721–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1982). The extended phenotype: The gene as the unit of selection. Oxford, USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dick S. J., & Strick J. E. (2005) The living Universe: NASA and the development of astrobiology. New Brunswick, New Jersey, and London: Rutgers University Press.

  • Dietrich, W., & Perron, J. (2006). The search for a topographic signature of life. Nature, 439(7075), 411–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doolittle, W. (1981). Is nature really motherly. CoEvolution Quarterly, 29, 58–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downing, K., & Zvirinsky, P. (1999). The simulated evolution of biochemical guilds: Reconciling Gaia theory and natural selection. Artificial Life, 5(4), 291–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutreuil, S. (2012). L’hypothèse Gaïa : Pourquoi s’y intéresser même si l’on pense que la Terre n’est pas un organisme? Bulletin de la société d’histoire et d’épistémologie des sciences de la vie, 19(2), 229–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutreuil, S., (2013) “Comment le modèle Daisyworld peut-il contribuer à l’hypothèse Gaïa?”. In F. Varenne & M. Silberstein (Eds.), Modéliser et simuler. Epistémologies et pratiques de la modélisation et de la simulation. Tome 1. Paris: Editions matériologiques.

  • Dyke, J., & Harvey, I. (2006). Pushing up the daisies. In L. M. Rocha (Ed.), Artificial Life X, proceedings of the tenth international conference on the simulation and synthesis of living systems (pp. 426–431). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyke, J., & Weaver, I. (2013). The emergence of environmental homeostasis in complex ecosystems. PLoS Computational Biology, 9(5), e1003050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P. (2010). Confirmation and explaining how possible. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41(1), 32–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franck, S., Block, A., VonBloh, W., et al. (2000). Reduction of biosphere life span as a consequence of geodynamics. Tellus B, 52(1), 94–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franck, S., Bounama, C., & VonBloh, W. (2006). Causes and timing of future biosphere extinctions. Biogeosciences, 3(1), 85–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Free, A., & Barton, N. (2007). Do evolution and ecology need the Gaia hypothesis? Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 22(11), 611–619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172(2), 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2010). Defining life: Synthesis and conclusions. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40(2), 231–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy, 21(5), 725–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Models and fictions in science. Philosophical Studies, 143(1), 101–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T., & Weirich, P. (2010). The philosophy and epistemology of simulation: A review. Simulation and Gaming, 41(1), 20–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, I. (2004). Homeostasis and rein control: From Daisyworld to active perception. In J. Pollack, et al. (Eds.), Proceedings of the ninth international conference on the simulation and synthesis of living systems, ALIFE (Vol. 9, pp. 309–314). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2009). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169(3), 615–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2010). Topological explanations and robustness in biological sciences. Synthese, 177(2), 213–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2012). Computer science meets evolutionary biology: Pure possible processes and the issue of gradualism. In O. Pombo, et al. (Eds.), Special sciences and the unity of science (pp. 137–162). Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchner, J. (1989). The Gaia hypothesis: Can it be tested. Review of Geophysics, 27(2), 223–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchner, J. (2002). The Gaia hypothesis: Fact, theory, and wishful thinking. Climatic Change, 52(4), 391–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchner, J. (2003). The Gaia hypothesis: Conjectures and refutations. Climatic Change, 58(1), 21–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). Science and pseudo science. In J. Worrall & G. Currie (Eds.), The methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. 1–7). Cambridge: Cambridge Unviersity Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (1996). Life, ‘artificial life’, and scientific explanation. Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenton, T., & Von Bloh, W. (2001). Biotic feedback extends the life span of the biosphere. Geophysical Research Letters, 28(9), 1715–1718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenton, T., & Williams, H. (2009). Gaia and Evolution. In E. Crist & H. B. Rinker (Eds.), Gaia in turmoil: Climate change, biodepletion, and earth ethics in an age of crisis (pp. 61–85). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2012). Models, fictions and realism: Two packages. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 738–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, K., Pahlevan, K., Kirschvink, J., & Yung, Y. (2009). Atmospheric pressure as a natural climate regulator for a terrestrial planet with a biosphere. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 106(24), 9576–9579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovelock, J. (1965). A physical basis for life detection experiments. Nature, 207, 568–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovelock, J. (1983). 1983, “Daisy world—a cybernetic proof of the Gaia hypothesis”. Coevolution Quarterly, Summer, 38, 66–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovelock, J., & Margulis, L. (1974). Atmospheric homeostasis by and for the biosphere: the Gaia hypothesis. Tellus, 26(1–2), 2–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovelock, J., & Whitfield, M. (1982). Life span of the biosphere. Nature, 296, 561–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K., & Weslake, B. (2013). Evolutionary theory and the epistemology of science. In K. Kampourakis (Ed.), The philosophy of biology: A companion for educators. Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDonald-Gibson, J., Dyke, J., DiPaolo, E., & Harvey, I. (2008). Environmental regulation can arise under minimal assumptions. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 251(4), 653–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morange, M. (2003). La Vie expliquée? : 50 ans après la double hélice. Paris: Odile Jacob.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., Shrader-Frechette, K., Belitz, K., et al. (1994). Verification, validation, and confirmation of numerical models in the earth sciences. Science, 263(5147), 641–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. S. (2009). Does matter really matter? Computer simulations, experiments, and materiality. Synthese, 169(3), 483–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2008). The borderlands between science and philosophy: An introduction. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 83(1), 7–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2013). On the different ways of’doing theory’ in biology. Biological Theory, 7(4), 287–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pocheville A., 2010, La niche écologique: concepts, modèles, applications. PhD thesis, Ecole Normale Supérieure, Ecole doctorale Frontières du Vivant.

  • Reydon, T. A. (2012). How-possibly explanations as genuine explanations and helpful heuristics: A comment on Forber. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(1), 302–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2013). The Gaia hypothesis: Science on a pagan planet. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S., & Plutynski, A. (2010). A Companion to the philosophy of biology. Hoboken, USA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheiner, S. M., & Willig, M. (2008). A general theory of ecology. Theoretical Ecology, 1(1), 21–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1991). Learning from functionalism: prospects for strong artificial life. In C. Langton, C. Taylor, J. D. Farmer, & S. Rasmussen (Eds.), Artificial Life II (pp. 749–766). Boulder: Oxford Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. New York, USA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2004). The causal and unification approaches to explanation unified—causally. Noûs, 38(1), 154–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, A. (1999). Coevolution of the Earth’s environment and life: Goldilocks, Gaia and the anthropic principle. In G. Y. Craig & J. H. Hull (Eds.), James Hutton—Present and Future. Geological Society (Vol. 150, pp. 75–88). London: Special Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, A., & Lovelock, J. (1983). Biological homeostasis of the global environment: The parable of Daisyworld. Tellus B, 35(4), 284–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weaver, I., & Dyke, J. (2012). The importance of timescales for the emergence of environmental self-regulation. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 313(21), 172–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2006). Robustness analysis. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 730–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(2), 207–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: using models to understand the world. New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, H., & Lenton, T. (2008). Environmental regulation in a network of simulated microbial ecosystems. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 105(30), 10432–10437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, H., & Noble, J. (2005). “Evolution and the regulation of environmental variables”. In M. S. Capcarrere., et al., Proceedings of VIIIth conference on Artificial Life (332–342). Berlin: Springer.

  • Winsberg, E. (2003). Simulated experiments: Methodology for a virtual world. Philosophy of Science, 70(1), 105–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2006). Models of success versus the success of models: Reliability without truth. Synthese, 152(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2009). A tale of two methods. Synthese, 169(3), 575–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. J., Ackland, G. J., Dyke, J. G., Williams, H. T., & Lenton, T. M. (2008). Daisyworld: A review. Reviews of Geophysics, 46(1).

  • Wood, A., Ackland, G., & Lenton, T. (2006). Mutation of albedo and growth reponse produced oscillations in a spatial Daisyworld. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 242, 188–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25(3), 287–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to all those present at the EASPLS meeting (Geneva, September 2012) and at the Duke Consortium for the history and philosophy of biology (June, 2013) for giving me their comments on these ideas, especially to Marie Kaiser and Tyler Curtain. I would like also to thank warmly Frédéric Bouchard, Jean Gayon, Philippe Huneman, Arnon Levy, Arnaud Pocheville and Judith Villez as well as an anonymous reviewer who helped me significantly improve earlier versions of this paper. I must finally thank Staffan Müller-Wille for his careful reading which has greatly contributed to the clarification and amelioration of the submitted version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sébastien Dutreuil.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dutreuil, S. What good are abstract and what-if models? Lessons from the Gaïa hypothesis. HPLS 36, 16–41 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-014-0003-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-014-0003-4

Keywords

Navigation