Skip to main content
Log in

Why Brains Are Not Computers, Why Behaviorism Is Not Satanism, and Why Dolphins Are Not Aquatic Apes

  • Original Article
  • Published:
The Behavior Analyst Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Modern psychology has, to all intents and purposes, become synonymous with cognitive psychology, with an emphasis on the idea that the brain is a form of computer, whose job is to take in sensory input, process information, and produce motor output. This places the brain at a remove from both the body and environment and denies the intimate connection that exists between them. As a result, a great injustice is done to both human and nonhuman animals: On the one hand, we fail to recognize the distinctive nature of nonhuman cognition, and on the other hand, we continue to promote a somewhat misleading view of human psychological capacities. Here, I suggest a more mutualistic, embodied, enactive view might allow us to ask more interesting questions about how animals of all kinds come to know their worlds, in ways that avoid the (inevitable) anthropocentric baggage of the cognitivist viewpoint.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Andrews, K. (2014). The animal mind: an introduction to the philosophy of Animal Cognition. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K., & Huss, B. (2014). Anthropomorphism, anthropectomy, and the null hypothesis. Biology & Philosophy, 29, 711–729.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2011). Beyond the brain: How body and environment shape animal and human minds. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2012). Why Behaviorism isn't Satanism. In J. Vonk & T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Comparative Evolutionary Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L., & Würsig, B. (2014). Why dolphins are not aquatic apes. Animal Behavior and Cognition, 1, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2015a). Back to the rough ground and into the hurly-burly. In: Mind, Language and Action: Proceedings of the 36th International Wittgenstein Symposium (Vol. 22, p. 299). Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG.

  • Barrett, L. (2015b). A better kind of continuity. S. J. Philos (in press)

  • Berns, G. (2013). Dogs are people, too. The New York Times, Oct 5.

  • Berns, G. S., Brooks, A. M., & Spivak, M. (2012). Functional MRI in awake unrestrained dogs. PLoS ONE, 7, e38027–7. 10.1371/journal.pone.0038027.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Berns, G. S., Brooks, A. M., & Spivak, M. (2015). Scent of the familiar: an fMRI study of canine brain responses to familiar and unfamiliar human and dog odors. Behavioural Processes, 110, 37–46.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bingham, G. P. (1988). Task-specific devices and the perceptual bottleneck. Human Movement Science, 7, 225–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, C. (1977). Mechanics of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S. (2007). Anthropomorphism and evidence. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 2, 145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artifical Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1999). Cambrian intelligence: the early history of the new AI. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2013). Morgan’s canon, meet Hume’s dictum: avoiding anthropofabulation in cross-species comparisons. Biology & Philosophy, 28(5), 853–871.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burghardt, G. M. (2007). Critical anthropomorphism, uncritical anthropocentrism, and naïve nominalism. Comparative Cognition and Behavior Reviews, 2, 136–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burrows, M., & Sutton, G. (2013). Interacting gears synchronize propulsive leg movements in a jumping insect. Science, 341(6151), 1254–1256.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, R. W., & Bates, L. A. (2006). Why are animals cognitive? Current Biology, 16(12), R445–R448.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Mindware: an introduction to the philosophy of cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2004). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2005). Beyond the flesh: some lessons from a mole cricket. Artificial Life, 11(1–2), 233–244.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, F. (1997). Are we in anthropodenial? scientists frown on thinking that animals have intentions and emotions. Yet how else can we really understand them? Discover-New York-, 18, 50–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emery, N. J. (2004). Are corvids “feathered apes.”. Comparative Analysis of Minds, 181, e213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Psychology Press.

  • Gravois, J. (2014) A toast story. http://www.psmag.com/health-and-behavior/toast-story-latest-artisanal-food-craze-72676. Accessed 5 Oct 2015.

  • Gregory, R. L. (1980). Perceptions as hypotheses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B: Biological Sciences, 290(1038), 181–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., & Tomasello, M. (2005). Human-like social skills in dogs? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(9), 439–444.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, G. R. (1996). Manufacture and use of hook-tools by New Caledonian crows. Nature, 379(6562), 249–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, G. R. (2000). Human–like, population–level specialization in the manufacture of pandanus tools by New Caledonian crows Corvus moneduloides. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 267(1441), 403–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2012). Radicalising enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, R. R., & Pollard, S. D. (1996). Predatory behavior of jumping spiders. Annual Review of Entomology, 41(1), 287–308.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Keeley, B. L. (2004). Anthropomorphism, primatomorphism, mammalomorphism: understanding cross-species comparisons. Biology & Philosophy, 19(4), 521–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsch, J. A., Güntürkün, O., & Rose, J. (2008). Insight without cortex: lessons from the avian brain. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(2), 475–483.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (1995). The intelligent use of space. Artificial Intelligence

  • Krupenye, C., Rosati, A. G., & Hare, B. (2015). Bonobos and chimpanzees exhibit human-like framing effects. Biology Letters, 11(2), 20140527–20140527.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Land, M. F. (1969). Movements of the retinae of jumping spiders (Salticidae: Dendryphantinae) in response to visual stimuli. Journal of Experimental Biology, 51(2), 471–493.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mace, W. M. (1977). James J. Gibson’s strategy for perceiving: Ask not what’s inside your head, but what your head’s inside of. Perceiving, Acting, and Knowing, 43–65.

  • Maravita, A., & Iriki, A. (2004). Tools for the body (schema). Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(2), 79–86.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Maravita, A., Spence, C., & Driver, J. (2003). Multisensory integration and the body schema: close to hand and within reach. Current Biology, 13(13), R531–R539.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Marino, L. (2002). Convergence of complex cognitive abilities in cetaceans and primates. Brain, Behavior and Evolution, 59(1–2), 21–32.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010). The extended mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Michel, K. B., Heiss, E., Aerts, P., & Van Wassenbergh, S. (2015). A fish that uses its hydrodynamic tongue to feed on land. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 282(1805), 20150057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, E. K. (2009). Behavior analysis and ecological psychology: past, present, and future. A review of harry Heft's ecological psychology in context. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 92, 275–304.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, S. T. (1990). Why big brains are so rare: Energy costs of intelligence and brain size in anthropoid primates (pp. 129–156). Comparative Developmental Perspectives: Language and Intelligence in Monkeys and Apes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, R., & Bongard, J. (2007). How the body shapes the way we think: a new view of intelligence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (2010). The cybernetic brain: Sketches of another future. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Porter, M. M., Adriaens, D., Hatton, R. L., Meyers, M. A., & McKittrick, J. (2015). Why the seahorse tail is square. Science, 349, aaa6683.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., Gallup, G. G., Eddy, J. R., Bierschwale, T. D., Engstrom, M. C., Perilloux, H. K., & Toxopeus, I. B. (1997). Chimpanzees recognize themselves in mirrors. Animal Behaviour, 53, 1083–1088.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, D., & Marino, L. (2001). Mirror self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin: a case of cognitive convergence. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 98, 5937–5942.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Scheier, C., & Pfeifer, R. (1995). Classification as sensory-motor coordination. In Advances in Artificial Life (pp. 657–667). Springer Berlin Heidelberg.

  • Scheier, C., & Pfeifer, R. (1998). Exploiting embodiment for category learning. In From animals to animats 5: Proceedings of the fifth international conference on simulation of adaptive behavior. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarsitano, M. (2006). Route selection by a jumping spider (Portia labiata) during the locomotory phase of a detour. Animal Behaviour, 72, 1437–1442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarsitano, M. S., & Jackson, R. R. (1994). Jumping spiders make predatory detours requiring movement away from prey. Behaviour, 131, 65–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarsitano, M. S., & Jackson, R. R. (1997). Araneophagic jumping spiders discriminate between detour routes that do and do not lead to prey. Animal Behaviour, 53, 257–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teschke, I., Wascher, C. A. F., Scriba, M. F., von Bayern, A. M. P., Huml, V., Siemers, B., & Tebbich, S. (2013). Did tool-use evolve with enhanced physical cognitive abilities? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B: Biological Sciences, 368(1630), 20120418.

    Article  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Timberlake, W. (2007). Anthropomorphism revisited. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 2, 139–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonneau, F. (2011). Metaphor and truth: a review of representation reconsidered by William Ramsay. Behavior & Philosophy, 39, 331–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Triantafyllou, M. S., & Triantafyllou, G. S. (1995). An efficient swimming machine. Scientific American, 272, 64–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Troscianko, J., von Bayern, A. M., Chappell, J., Rutz, C., & Martin, G. R. (2012). Extreme binocular vision and a straight bill facilitate tool use in New Caledonian crows. Nature Communications, 3, 1110.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Tyler, T. (2003). If horses had hands…. Society & Animals, 11, 267–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uexküll, Von, J. (2014). Umwelt und innenwelt der tiere. Springer-Verlag

  • Wynne, C. D. (2007). What are animals? Why anthropomorphism is still not a scientific approach to behavior. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 2, 125–135.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Louise Barrett.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Thanks to Chris Newland for the invitation to present as a B.F. Skinner lecturer at the ABAI conference in Chicago 2015 and to Matthew Normand for inviting me to submit a paper, based on my talk, to this journal. Thanks also to Chris, Tim Hackenberg, Jon Pinkston, John Malone, Andrés García-Penagos, and Christina Nord for interesting discussions of the issues raised in this paper, Gert Stulp for helpful comments on an earlier draft, and Jessica Parker for editorial help. Funding for my work comes from the Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada’s Discovery Grant and Canada Research Chair programs.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Barrett, L. Why Brains Are Not Computers, Why Behaviorism Is Not Satanism, and Why Dolphins Are Not Aquatic Apes. BEHAV ANALYST 39, 9–23 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-015-0047-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-015-0047-0

Keywords

Navigation