Advertisement

Biological Theory

, Volume 13, Issue 2, pp 121–130 | Cite as

Why We Should Care About Universal Biology

  • Carlos Mariscal
  • Leonore Fleming
Thematic Issue Article: Astrobiology

Abstract

Our understanding of the universe has grown rapidly in recent decades. We’ve discovered evidence of water in nearby planets, discovered planets outside our solar system, mapped the genomes of thousands of organisms, and probed the very origins and limits of life. The scientific perspective of life-as-it-could-be has expanded in part by research in astrobiology, synthetic biology, and artificial life. In the face of such scientific developments, we argue there is an ever-growing need for universal biology, life-as-it-must-be, the multidisciplinary study of non-contingent aspects of life as guided by biological theory and constrained by the universe. We present three distinct but connected ways of universalizing biology—with respect to characterizing aspects of life everywhere, with respect to the explanatory scope of biological theory, and with respect to extending biological insights to the structure of nonbiological entities. For each of these, we sketch the theoretical goals and challenges, as well as give examples of current research that might be labeled universal biology.

Keywords

Astrobiology Cosmological natural selection Definition of life Extended evolutionary synthesis Minimal genome Universal biology 

Notes

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank Kelly C. Smith and several anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and suggestions.

References

  1. Bagg S (2017) When will a Darwinian approach be useful for the study of society? Polit Philos Econ. doi: 10.1177/1470594X16687839 Google Scholar
  2. Barrett PH, Gautrey PJ, Herbert S, Kohn D, Smith S (eds) (1987) Charles Darwin’s notebooks, 1836–1844: Geology, transmutation of species, metaphysical enquiries. British Museum (Natural History). Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  3. Beatty J (1995) The evolutionary contingency thesis. In: Lennox JG, Wolters G (eds) Concepts, theories and rationality in the biological sciences. University of Konstanz Press, Konstanz & University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 45–81Google Scholar
  4. Benner SA (2010) Defining life. Astrobiology 10(10):1021–1030. doi: 10.1089/ast.2010.0524 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bonner JT (2011) Why size matters: from bacteria to blue whales. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  6. Booth A, Mariscal C, Doolittle WF (2016) The modern synthesis in the light of microbial genomics. Annu Rev Microbiol 70(1):279–297CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bouchard F, Huneman P (2013) From groups to individuals: evolution and emerging individuality. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  8. Brandon RN (1997) Does biology have laws? The experimental evidence. Philos Sci 64(Suppl):S444–S457CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Breitbart M, Rohwer F (2005) Here a virus, there a virus, everywhere the same virus? Trends Microbiol 13(6):278–284CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Brooks DR, Wiley EO (1988) Evolution as entropy. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  11. Bruylants G, Bartik K, Reisse J (2010) Is it useful to have a clear-cut definition of life? On the use of fuzzy logic in prebiotic chemistry. Orig Life Evolut Biosph 40(2):137–143CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Chou F, Johnson M (2016) NASA’s Kepler mission announces largest collection of planets ever discovered. NASA May 10, 2016, Press Release. http://www.nasa.gov/press-release/nasas-kepler-mission-announces-largest-collection-of-planets-ever-discovered. Accessed 27 June 2016
  13. Cleland CE, Chyba CF (2002) Defining “life”. Orig Life Evolut Biosph 32(4):387–393CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Coyle M, Hu J, Gartner Z (2016) Mysteries in a minimal genome. ACS Cent Sci 2(5):274–277CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  16. Dawkins R (1982) Universal Darwinism. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution from molecules to men. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 403–425Google Scholar
  17. Descartes R ([1633]2010) Treatise on man. In: Bedau MA, Cleland CE (eds) The nature of life: classical and contemporary perspectives from philosophy and science. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  18. Diéguez A (2013) Life as a homeostatic property cluster. Biol Theory 7(2):180–186CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Dray W (1957) Laws and explanation in history. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  20. Dupré J (2014) A process ontology for biology. Philos Mag 67:81–88Google Scholar
  21. Dupré J, Guttinger S (2016) Viruses as living processes. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsc.2016.02.010 Google Scholar
  22. England JL (2013) Statistical physics of self-replication. J Chem Phys 139:121923CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Fiers W, Contreras R, Duerinck F et al (1976) Complete nucleotide sequence of bacteriophage MS2 RNA: primary and secondary structure of the replicase gene. Nature 260(5551):500–507CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Fleming L (2012) Network theory and the formation of groups without evolutionary forces. Evol Biol 39(1):94–105. doi: 10.1007/s11692-011-9140-9 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Fleming L, Brandon R (2015) Why flying dogs are rare: a general theory of luck in the evolutionary transitions. Stud Hist Philos Sci C 49:24–31. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsc.2014.10.006 Google Scholar
  26. Gardner A (2014) Life, the universe and everything. Biol Philos 29(2):207–215CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Gardner A, Conlon JP (2013) Cosmological natural selection and the purpose of the universe. Complexity 18:48–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Gray MW, Doolittle WF (1982) Has the endosymbiont hypothesis been proven? Microbiol Rev 46(1):1Google Scholar
  29. Hermida M (2016) Life on Earth is an individual. Theory Biosci 135(1–2):37–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Irwin LN, Schulze-Makuch D (2011) Cosmic biology: how life could evolve on other worlds. Praxis, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Jabr F (2013) Why life does not really exist. Scientific American. http://blogs.scientificamerican.com/brainwaves/2013/12/02/why-life-does-not-really-exist/. Accessed 29 May 2014
  32. Jonsson KI, Rabbow E, Schill RO, Harms-Ringdahl M, Rettberg P (2008) Tardigrades survive exposure to space in low earth orbit. Curr Biol 18:R729–R731CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Joyce GF (1994) Foreword. In: Deamer DW, Fleischaker GR (eds) Origins of life: the central concepts. Jones & Bartlett, Boston, pp xi–xiiGoogle Scholar
  34. Kauffman S (1993) The origins of order: self organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  35. Kauffman S (1995) At home in the universe: the search for laws of self-organization and complexity. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  36. Kauffman S (2000) Investigations. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  37. Kay LE (1992) The molecular vision of life: Caltech, the Rockefeller Foundation, and the Rise of the New Biology. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  38. Koonin EV (2000) How many genes can make a cell: the minimal-gene-Set concept 1. Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet 1(1):99–116CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Kowalski H (2016) First minimal synthetic bacterial cell designed and constructed by Scientists at Venter Institute and Synthetic Genomics, Inc. March 24, 2016, Press Release. http://www.jcvi.org/cms/press/press-releases/full-text/article/first-minimal-synthetic-bacterial-cell-designed-and-constructed-by-scientists-at-venter-institute-an/. Accessed 25 June 2016
  40. Lafferty KD, Dobson AP, Kuris AM (2006) Parasites dominate food web links. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 103(30):11211–11216CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Laland KN, Uller T, Feldman MW et al (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Yes, urgently. Nature 514(7521):161–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Laland KN, Uller T, Feldman MW et al (2015) The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proc R Soc B 282:20151019CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Lange M (2002) Who’s afraid of ceteris-paribus laws? Or: how I learned to stop worrying and love them. Erkenntnis 57(3):407–423CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Langton CG (ed) (1989) Artificial life. Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, Redwood CityGoogle Scholar
  45. Machery E (2011) Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life … and why you should as well. Synthese 185:145–164Google Scholar
  46. McGuire BA, Carroll PB, Loomis RA et al (2016) Discovery of the interstellar chiral molecule propylene oxide (CH3CHCH2O). Science 352(6292):1449–1452CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. McShea DW (2012) Upper-directed systems: a new approach to teleology in biology. Biol Philos 27:663e684CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. McShea DW (2016) Freedom and purpose in biology. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 58:64–72. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsc.2015.12.002 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. McShea DW, Brandon RN (2010) Biology’s First Law: the tendency for diversity & complexity to increase in evolutionary systems. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Mitchell SD (1997) Pragmatic laws. Philos Sci 64(4):479Google Scholar
  51. Morris JJ, Lenski RE, Zinser ER (2012) The Black Queen Hypothesis: evolution of dependencies through adaptive gene loss. MBio 3(2):e00036-12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Munson R (1975) Is biology a provincial science? Philos Sci 42(4):428–447CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Nagel E (1979) Teleology revisited and other essays in the philosophy an history of science. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  54. Nesbø CL, Dlutek M, Doolittle WF (2006) Recombination in Thermotoga: implications for species concepts and biogeography. Genetics 172(2):759–769CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Newman SA (1970) Note on complex systems. J Theor Biol 28:411–413CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Öberg KI, Guzmán VV, Furuya K et al (2015) The comet-like composition of a protoplanetary disk as revealed by complex cyanides. Nature 520(7546):198. doi: 10.1038/nature14276 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Ojha L, Wilhelm MB, Murchie SL et al (2015) Spectral evidence for hydrated salts in recurring slope lineae on Mars. Nat Geosci 8(11):829–832CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Pigliucci M (2009) An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1168(1):218–228CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Pigliucci MM, Müller GB (2010) Evolution—the extended synthesis. MIT Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Popper KR (1976) Unended quest: an intellectual autobiography. Open Court, LaSalleGoogle Scholar
  61. Popper KR (1978) Natural selection and the emergence of mind. Dialectica 32:339–355Google Scholar
  62. Powell R, Mariscal C (2015) Convergent evolution as natural experiment: the tape of life reconsidered. Interface focus 5(6):20150040CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Rice SH (2004) Evolutionary theory: mathematical and conceptual foundations. Sinauer, SunderlandGoogle Scholar
  64. Rosenberg A (1984) The supervenience of biological concepts. In: Sober E (ed) Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology. Bradford Books-MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 99–116Google Scholar
  65. Scharf C, Virgo N, Cleaves HJ et al (2015) A strategy for origins of life research. Astrobiology 15(12):1031–1042CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Sczepanski JT, Joyce GF (2014) A cross-chiral RNA polymerase ribozyme. Nature 515(7527):440–442CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Shapiro R, Feinberg G (1980) Life beyond Earth: the intelligent earthling’s guide to life in the universe. William Morrow, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  68. Smart JJC (1963) Philosophy and scientific realism. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  69. Smart JJC (1968) Between science and philosophy. Random House, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  70. Smith KC (2016) Life is hard: countering definitional pessimism concerning the definition of life. Int J Astrobiol 15(4):277–289. doi: 10.1017/S1473550416000021 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Smolin L (1992) Did the universe evolve? Class Quantum Gravity 9:173–191CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Smolin L (1997) The life of the cosmos. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  73. Sommerhoff G (1950) Analytical biology. Oxford University Press, LondonGoogle Scholar
  74. Sterelny K, Griffiths P (1999) Sex and death: an introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  75. Trifonov EN (2011) Vocabulary of definitions of life suggests a definition. J Biomol Struct Dyn 29(2):259–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Ulanowicz RE (2003) On the ordinality of causes in complex autocatalytic systems. Ann N Y Acad Sci 988:154–157CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Walsh C, Loomis RA, Öberg KI et al (2016) First detection of gas-phase methanol in a protoplanetary disk. Astrophys J Lett 823(1):L10CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Waters E, Hohn MJ, Ahel I et al (2003) The genome of Nanoarchaeum equitans: insights into early archaeal evolution and derived parasitism. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 100(22):12984–12988CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Welikala N, Béthermin M, Guery D et al (2016) Probing star formation in the dense environments of z ~ 1 lensing haloes aligned with dusty star-forming galaxies detected with the South Pole Telescope. Mon Not R Astron Soc 455(2):1629–1646CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  80. Wray AE, Hoekstra HE, Futuyma DJ et al (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? No, all is well. Nature 514(7521):161–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of NevadaRenoUSA
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyUtica CollegeUticaUSA

Personalised recommendations