Skip to main content
Log in

Taking Stock of Extension Theory of Technology

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Philosophy & Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I will focus on the extension theories of technology. I will identify four influential positions that have been put forward: (1) technology as an extension of the human organism, (2) technology as an extension of the lived body and the senses, (3) technology as an extension of our intentions and desires, and (4) technology as an extension of our faculties and capabilities. I will describe and critically assess these positions one by one and highlight their advantages and their shortcomings and limitations. Along the way, I will explicate some of the differences and similarities between the various approaches. I conclude the paper with some suggestions for future research directions that will be beneficial for advancing theory building and that will drive forward the philosophical refinement of extension theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Eudemian Ethics book 7, 1241 b.

  2. A similar point has been raised by Brey (2000). He gives some counterexamples to the alleged morphological projection of human organs: lighters, telephones, and fishing nets.

  3. It is important to note that cups and books can be used as an extension of the senses. We can imagine someone using a book in the same way a blind man uses his cane. Technologies cannot be reduced to a designed intent; rather they are ambiguous and can be embedded in a variety of ways. Or as Ihde (1990) calls it, technologies are “multistable” (144). See also Ihde (2002), 106.

  4. For a more detailed comparison of Kapp and Rothenberg, see Brey (2000).

  5. In some cases, however, technology may be the only way to realize an intention. Think of the desire to propel subatomic particles and the intention to fulfill this desire. Here, the use of a particle accelerator is inevitable.

  6. I do not share Lawson’s (2008) verdict that Brey leaves his notion of extension unclear.

  7. Further advantages of the capabilities account are that it helps to explain the evolutionary trajectory of technology, that it raises the question whether our extension are in line with our desires and what consequences the extension of faculties has for our self-understanding. For more, see Brey (2000).

  8. I take this idea from the debate on extended mind and the bounds of cognition. See, for example, Adams and Aizawa (2008).

  9. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for bringing this to my attention.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen-Hermanson, S. (2012). Superdupersizing the mind: extended cognition and the persistence of cognitive bloat. Philosophical Studies, 158(1), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bejjanki, V. R., Zhang, R., Li, R., Pouget, A., Green, C. S., Lu, Z.-L., & Bavelier, D. (2014). Action video game play facilitates the development of better perceptual templates. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. doi:10.1073/pnas.1417056111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belk, R. W. (2013). Extended self in a digital world. Journal of Consumer Research, 40(3), 477–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besmer, K. (2012). Embodying a translation technology: the cochlear implant and cyborg intentionality. Techné, 16(3), 296–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. (2006). Mind as machine. A history of cognitive science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosco, R., & Wilson, D. E. (Eds.). (2007). Collected works of Ralph Waldo Emerson, Vol. 7: society and solitude. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brey, P. (2000). Technology as extension of human faculties. In C. Mitcham (Ed.), Metaphysics, epistemology, and technology. Research in philosophy and technology (pp. 59–78). London: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, N. G. (2011). The shallows: what the Internet is doing to our brains. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2007). Re-inventing ourselves: the plasticity of embodiment, sensing, and mind. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32(3), 263–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Preester, H. (2011). Technology and the body: the (im)possibilities of re-embodiment. Foundations of Science, 16(2), 119–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Preester, H., & Tsakiris, M. (2009). Body-extension versus body-incorporation: is there a need for a body-model? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(3), 307–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002). Intelligence without representation—Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. The relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, S. E. (2004). The five-stage model of adult skill acquisition. Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society, 24(3), 177–181. doi:10.1177/0270467604264992.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feibleman, J. K. (1966). Technology as skills. Technology and Culture, 7(3), 318–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feibleman, J. K. (1967). The philosophy of tools. Social Forces, 45(3), 329–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feibleman, J. K. (1979). Technology and human nature. Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, 10(1), 35–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granic, I., Lobel, A., & Engels, R. C. M. E. (2014). The benefits of playing video games. American Psychologist, 69(1), 66–78. doi:10.1037/a0034857.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heersmink, R. (2012). Defending extension theory: a response to Kiran and Verbeek. Philosophy and Technology, 25(1), 121–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heersmink, R. (2014). Dimensions of integration in embedded and extended cognitive systems. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-014-9355-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (1990). Technology and the lifeworld. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (2002). Bodies in technology. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D., & Selinger, E. (2004). Merleau-Ponty and epistemology engines. Human Studies, 27(4), 361–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapp, E. (1877). Grundlinien einer Philosophie der Technik. Zur Entstehungsgeschichte der Cultur aus neuen Gesichtspunkten. Westermann: Braunschweig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiran, A. H., & Verbeek, P.-P. (2010). Trusting our selves to technology. Knowledge, Technology and Policy, 23(3–4), 409–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, C. (2008). An ontology of technology. Techné, 12(1), 48–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, C. (2010). Technology and the extension of human capabilities. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 40(2), 207–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1985). Philosophical essays. Translated and edited by Roger Ariew and Dan Garber. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • McCarthy, J., & Wright, P. (2004). Technology as experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLuhan, M. (1964). Understanding media: the extensions of man. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2006). Attacking the bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 19(3), 329–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitcham, C. (1994). Thinking through technology. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neely, E. L. (2013). Machines and the moral community. Philosophy & Technology, 27(1), 97–111. doi:10.1007/s13347-013-0114-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1973). Psychological predicates. In D. D. Capitan & W. H. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–49). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothenberg, D. (1995). Hand's end. Technology and the limits of nature. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Eede, Y. (2014). Extending “Extension.”. In A. D. Propen, D. M. Weiss, & C. E. Reid (Eds.), Design, mediation, and the posthuman (pp. 151–171). Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, P.-P. (2008). Obstetric ultrasound and the technological mediation of morality: a postphenomenological analysis. Human Studies, 31(1), 11–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2010). In defence of extended functionalism. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 245–270). MIT Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Tanja Hentschel and Felicitas Selter for feedback on earlier drafts, as well as one anonymous reviewer for valuable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steffen Steinert.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Steinert, S. Taking Stock of Extension Theory of Technology. Philos. Technol. 29, 61–78 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-014-0186-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-014-0186-3

Keywords

Navigation