Abstract
The aim of this paper is to address the neglected but important problem of differentiating between epistemically beneficial and epistemically detrimental dissent. By “dissent,” we refer to the act of objecting to a particular conclusion, especially one that is widely held. While dissent in science can clearly be beneficial, there might be some instances of dissent that not only fail to contribute to scientific progress, but actually impede it. Potential examples of this include the tobacco industry’s funding of studies that questioned the link between smoking and lung cancer, and the attempt by the petroleum industry and other groups to cast doubt upon the conclusion that human consumption of fossil fuels contributes to global climate change. The problem of distinguishing between good and bad dissent is important because of the growing tendency of some stakeholders to attempt to delay political action by ’manufacturing doubt’ (Oreskes & Conway 2010). Our discussion in this paper focuses on climate science. This field, in our view, is rife with instances of bad dissent. On the basis of our discussion of climate science, we articulate a set of sufficient conditions for epistemically problematic dissent in general, which we call “the inductive risk account of epistemically detrimental dissent.”
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
By referring to “climate skeptics” we do not mean “skeptical climate scientists” who merely “hold a skeptical view of the validity and utility of [climate …] models”; in Myanna Lahsen's and Riley E. Dunlap's terminology we are discussing the case of “dissident” or “contrarian scientists” who “strongly criticize climate science and in many cases participate in the denial machine” (Dunlap 2013, p. 693; cf. also Lahsen 2008).
http://www.grida.no/publications/other/ipcc_tar/?src=/climate/ipcc_tar/wg1/005.htm. Accessed 19 April 2014.
http://www8.nationalacademies.org/onpinews/newsitem.aspx?RecordID=11676. Accessed 19 April 2014.
http://sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0167947307002861#. Accessed 19 April 2014.
There is no evidence, as far as we are aware, that the dissenting scientists are directly responsible for threats to personal well being or death threats. However, the dissent – and particularly the ways in which that dissent is used by some politicians and media outlets – helps to create the conditions for such threats.
The terminology of ‘producer risks’ and ‘public risks’ is a variant on that of ‘producer’ and ‘consumer’ risks. Producer risks are risks of wrongly accepting hypotheses, when doing so would primarily harm producers; consumer risks are risks of wrongly rejecting hypotheses, when doing so would primarily harm consumers. The phrases ‘producer’ and ‘consumer risks’ are typically used in the context of technology assessment and policy-relevant science. We use the phrase ‘public risks’ instead of ‘consumer risks,’ because there are consequences that fall primarily on the public, even if they do not result from consuming any particular product.
Particularly Kuhn (1977, p. 332) pointed out that the choice of methodological standards in science is influenced by contextual, non-epistemic preferences of scientists. Note that this does not mean that these standards are arbitrary. It merely means that the choice of methodological standards is empirically underdetermined and hence influenced to some degree by non-epistemic values. Longino (2002), pp. 130–131) also stresses that criticism in science can only be fruitful when it fulfills conventional (“public”) standards.
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging us to elaborate on this.
We are grateful to Torsten Wilholt for discussion on this point.
Traditionally, philosophers of science have not viewed dissemination as being epistemically significant; on this view, confirmation and testing are matters for epistemology, while dissemination is a matter for sociology. We have argued, however, that the way in which dissent is disseminated can have a significant impact upon the progress of science.
References
AEI. (2007). Letter to senators Sanders, Feinstein, Leahy, and Kerry by Christopher DeMuth. http://www.christopherdemuth.com/letter-to-senators-sanders-feinstein-leahy-and-kerry.html. Accessed 19 April 2014.
Bekelman, J. E., Li, Y., & Gross, C. P. (2003). Scope and impact of financial conflicts of interest in biomedical research: A systematic review. Journal of the American Medical Association, 289(4), 454–465.
Biddle, J. (2007). Lessons from the vioxx debacle: What the privatization of science can teach us about social epistemology. Social Epistemology, 21, 21–39.
Biddle, J. (2013). State of the field: Transient underdetermination and values in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44(1), 124–133.
Biddle, J., & Winsberg, E. (2010). Value judgements and the estimation of uncertainty in climate modeling. In P. D. Magnus & J. Busch (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of science (pp. 172–197). Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan.
Bowen, M. (2008). Censoring science: Inside the political attack on Dr. James Hansen and the truth of global warming. New York: Dutton.
Brown, J. R. (2008). The community of science®. In M. Carrier, D. A. Howard, & J. Kourany (Eds.), The challenge of the social and the pressure of practice (pp. 189–216). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Brysse, K., Oreskes, N., O’Reilly, J., & Oppenheimer, M. (2012). Climate change prediction: Erring on the side of least drama? Global Environmental Change, 23, 327–337.
Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 559–579.
Dunlap, R. E. (2013). Climate change skepticism and denial: An introduction. American Behavioral Scientist, 57(6), 691–698.
Dunlap, R. E., & Jacques, P. J. (2013). Climate change denial books and conservative think tanks: Exploring the connection. American Behavioral Scientist, 57, 699–731.
Elliott, K. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Elsasser, S. W., & Dunlap, R. E. (2013). Leading voices in the denier choir: Conservative columnists’ dismissal of global warming and denigration of climate science. American Behavioral Scientist, 57(6), 754–776.
Freudenburg, W. R., & Muselli, V. (2010). Global warming estimates, media expectations, and the asymmetry of scientific challenge. Global Environmental Change, 20, 483–491.
Gelbspan, R. (1997). The heat is on. New York: Perseus Books.
IPCC (1995). Climate change 1995: A report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. https://www.ipcc.ch/pdf/climate-changes-1995/ipcc-2nd-assessment/2nd-assessment-en.pdf. Accessed 19 April 2014.
IPCC (2013). Summary for policy makers. In T. F. Stocker, D. Qin, G.-K. Plattner, M. Tignor, S. K. Allen, J. Boschung, A. Nauels, Y. Xia, V. Bex & P. M. Midgley (Eds.), Climate change 2013: The physical science basis. Contribution of working group I to the fifth assessment report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge, UK, and New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Jacques, P. J., Dunlap, R. E., & Freeman, M. (2008). The organization of denial: Conservative think tanks and environmental skepticism. Environmental Politics, 17, 349–385.
Jeffrey, R. (1956). Valuation and acceptance of scientific hypotheses. Philosophy of Science, 23(3), 237–246.
Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kitcher, P. (2011). Science in a democratic society. New York: Prometheus Books.
Krimsky, S. (2003). Science in the private interest: Has the lure of profits corrupted biomedical research? Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press
Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In The essential tension: selected studies in scientific tradition and change (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lahsen, M. (2008). Experiences of modernity in the greenhouse. A cultural analysis of a physicist “trio” supporting the backlash against global warming. Global Environmental Change, 18, 204–219.
Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Levi, I. (1960). Must the scientist make value judgments? The Journal of Philosophy, 57(11), 345–357.
Lewandowsky, S., Gignac, G. E., & Oberauer, K. (2013). The role of conspiracist ideation and worldviews in predicting rejection of science. PloS One, 8(10), e75637.
Lloyd, E. A. (2012). The role of ‘complex’ empiricism in the debates about satellite data and climate models. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 43(2), 390–401.
Longino, H. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Mann, M. (2012). The hockey stick and the climate wars. dispatches from the front lines. New York: Columbia University Press.
Mann, M. E., Bradley, R. S., & Hughes, M. K. (1998). Global-scale temperature patterns and climate forcing over the past six centuries. Nature, 392, 779–787.
Mann, M. E., Bradley, R. S., & Hughes, M. K. (1999). Northern-hemisphere temperatures during the past millennium: Inferences, uncertainties, and limitations. Geophysical Research Letters, 26, 759–762.
McGarity, T. O., & Wagner, W. E. (2008). Bending science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
McIntyre, S., & McKitrick, R. (2003). Corrections to Mann et al. [1998] proxy database and northern hemisphere average temperature series. Energy and Environment, 14, 751–771.
McIntyre, S. & McKitrick, R. (2005). Hockey sticks, principle components, and spurious significance. Geophysical Research Letters 32, L03710
NRC. (2009). Restructuring federal climate research to meet the challenges of climate change. Washington: The National Academies Press.
Oreskes, N. (2004). The scientific consensus on climate change. Science, 306, 1686.
Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. (2010). Merchants of doubt. New York: Bloomsbury Press.
Proctor, R., & Schiebinger, L. (2008). Agnotology: The making and unmaking of ignorance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Rahmstorf, S., Cazenave, A., Church, J. A., Hansen, J. E., Keeling, R. F., Parker, D. E., & Somerville, R. C. J. (2007). Recent climate observations compared to projections. Science, 316, 709.
Regalado, A. (2005). In climate debate, the ‘hockey stick’ leads to a face-off. Wall Street Journal (February 14). http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB110834031507653590. Accessed 15 May 2014.
Rudner, R. (1953). The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science, 20(1), 1–6.
Rutherford, S., Mann, M. E., Osborn, T. J., Bradley, R. S., Briffa, K. R., Hughes, M. K., & Jones, P. D. (2005). Proxy-based northern hemisphere surface temperature reconstructions: Sensitivity to method, predictor network, target season, and target domain. Journal of Climate, 18, 2308–2329.
Schneider, S. (2009). Science as a contact sport: Inside the battle to save earth’s climate. Washington: National Geographic Society.
Sills, J. (2010). Climate change and the integrity of science. Science, 328, 689–691.
Sismondo, S. (2007). Ghost management: How much of the medical literature is shaped behind the scenes by the pharmaceutical industry? PLoS Medicine, 4(9), e286.
UNEP (2009). Climate change science compendium 2009. http://www.unep.org/pdf/ccScienceCompendium2009/cc_ScienceCompendium2009_full_highres_en.pdf. Accessed 19 April 2014
Vom Saal, F. S., & Hughes, C. (2005). An extensive new literature concerning low-dose effects of bisphenol a shows the need for a new risk assessment. Environmental Health Perspectives, 113(8), 926–933.
Wahl, E. R., & Ammann, C. M. (2007). Robustness of the Mann, Bradley, and Hughes reconstruction of northern hemisphere surface temperatures: examination of criticisms based on the nature and processing of proxy climate evidence. Climatic Change, 85, 33–69.
Wilholt, T. (2009). Bias and values in scientific research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 40(1), 92–101.
Acknowledgments
Each author is responsible for the paper in its entirety, and both authors contributed equally to the final product. Earlier drafts of this paper were presented at Bielefeld University, Tilburg University, Georgia Institute of Technology, and the GAP.8 conference at the University of Konstanz. We would particularly like to thank Paul Baer, Gregor Betz, Sebastian Cacean, Martin Carrier, Matt Cox, Michael Hoffmann, Paul Hoyningen-Huene, Philip Kitcher, Frederike Neuber, Bryan Norton, Naomi Oreskes, Juha Saatsi, Christian Voigt, John Walsh, Torsten Wilholt, and Eric Winsberg for their valuable comments. Thanks also to the Notre Dame Institute for Advanced Study for support.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Biddle, J.B., Leuschner, A. Climate skepticism and the manufacture of doubt: can dissent in science be epistemically detrimental?. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 5, 261–278 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-014-0101-x
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-014-0101-x