Skip to main content
Log in

Remembering: Epistemic and Empirical

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The construct “remembering” is equivocal between an epistemic sense, denoting a distinctive ground for knowledge, and empirical sense, denoting the typical behavior of a neurocognitive mechanism. Because the same kind of equivocation arises for other psychologistic terms (such as believe, decide, know, judge, decide, infer and reason), the effort to spot and remedy the confusion in the case of remembering might prove generally instructive. The failure to allow these two senses of remembering equal play in their respective domains leads, I argue, to unnecessary confusion about memory externalism, the possibility of episodic memory in non-human species, and the thesis of memory continuism. By distinguishing these equivocal senses of remembering, we thus gain leverage on understanding how the distinctive epistemic norms that define many of our psychologic terms are more plausibly related to the capacities studied by empirical science, given that neither identity nor elimination are possible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These words, empirical and epistemic, should not be given undue exegetical weight, especially the latter. I chose them as a satisficing gesture toward the set of practices and norms in terms of which these senses of remembering are understood. I do not mean to suggest, falsely, that all and only epistemologists have the epistemic view. I resisted casting the distinction as between philosophical versus scientific views precisely because the dominant view in the philosophy of memory these days is the empirical view. I might have described it as normative versus empirical, but norms in some sense are involved in the empirical as well, as explained below. I might have correctly described the epistemic as factive, but the epistemic as I envision it is more than a claim to factivity but an assertion of epistemic privilege. I might have described it as illocutionary, though I leave it open whether non-linguistic creatures epistemically remember. The contrast is emphatically not between an ordinary use of the concept and a technical one, as both senses under discussion here are perfectly ordinary and marked in everyday speech: “I remember putting my cameo in the drawer, but I guess I might have put it on the shelf” expresses an empirical sense; “But remember, Petty Larceny won in the eighth, so the jockey couldn’t have been in the shop then” expresses the epistemic sense. They are also both deployed in technical contexts (in a laboratory or a court of law, respectively) in ways that admit of and benefit from careful analysis and delimitation.

  2. Apologies to Haugeland (1998), who uses this phrase for a different and unrelated phenomenon.

  3. I allow below that one might normatively remember without empirically remembering in the way humans typically do.

  4. Sarah Robins explores the various constraints at work in this space and their interactions with philosophical theories of remembering in (Robins 2016a, 2016b, 2019)

  5. The language here is borrowed from Brandom (1994).

  6. Unlike the causal theory of memory (Martin and Deutscher 1966), an epistemic theory need not require that the event as represented now is sufficiently similar to the event as experienced then. One might argue that the causal requirement in the causal theory is an unnecessary empirical contamination from the epistemic stance, one that sends us searching for a well-identified engram encoding the past. Success in remembering might, as an empirical matter of fact, require such a causal structure, and tracing that causal structure might therefore be crucial evidence concerning whether one does or does not remember (drinks at the lounge, pressure at testimony from the gang, or improper interrogation techniques), but success in remembering can be specified completely without mentioning the word cause or appeal to a trace, for that matter, though these may be empirically necessary. The relationship between this commitment-based view and the causal theory requires an extended treatment of its own.

  7. The remember/know distinction tracks inner experience thought to correlate with the difference between episodic and semantic memory, but not the distinction between remembering and seeming to remember. Secondly, I allow that norms of remembering can vary across times and cultures, embedding remembering and claims to remember in a different set of commitments and entitlements. This would make a fantastically interesting study. Finally, Philosophers of memory have tended to be interested in epistemology. Sue Campbell (2014) argues rightly that there are normative dimensions of remembering beyond truth; the norms of remembering emotions also deserve full exploration.

  8. See Roediger et al. 1990.

  9. This is so even if there are success conditions in both cases. The empirical memory capacity, the capacity to construct scenes, let’s say, is something that might fail for one reason or another. One might be unable to generate details, for example. Or one might fail to bind those details into a coherent whole (see Keven 2018).

  10. This philosophical thought experiment is no mere idle curiosity to individuals with memory impairments who might hope to scaffold the epistemic functions threatened by their impairments with the use of external devices. In some cases, handheld devices make a qualitative difference to the kinds of life these people, in the fullest sense, can lead (see Craver and Rosenbaum 2018).

  11. Piccinini and Craver (2011), for example, are clearly focused on the norms of empirical, not normative, concept revision.

References

  • Addis, Donna Rose, Alana T. Wong, and Daniel L. Schacter. 2007. Remembering the past and imagining the future: Common and distinct neural substrates during event construction and elaboration. Neuropsychologia 45 (7): 1363–1377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atance, Cristina M., and Daniela K. O’Neill. 2001. Episodic future thinking. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5 (12): 533–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 1995. Memorial justification. Philosophical Topics 23 (1): 31–45. https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics199523123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett, Frederic C. 1932. 1995, Remembering: A Study in Experimental and Social Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernecker, Sven. 2010. Memory: A philosophical study. Oxford University Press.

  • Boyer, Pascal. 2008. Evolutionary economics of mental time travel? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12 (6): 219–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, Randy L., and Daniel C. Carroll. 2007. Self-projection and the brain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11 (2): 49–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borghini, Andrea, and Giuliano Torrengo. 2013. “The Metaphysics of the Thin Red Line.” In Around the Tree, 105–125. Springer.

  • Campbell, Sue. 2014. Our faithfulness to the past: The ethics and politics of memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199376933.001.0001.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Hasok. 2004. Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific Progress. Oxford University Press.

  • Clark, Andy, and David Chalmers. 1998. “The Extended Mind.” Analysis, 7–19.

  • Clayton, Nicola S., and Anthony Dickinson. 1998. Episodic-like memory during cache recovery by scrub jays. Nature 395 (6699): 272–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, Carl F. 2007. Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford University Press.

  • Craver, Carl F., and R. Shayna Rosenbaum. 2018. Consent Without Memory 1. New Directions in the Philosophy of Memory. Routledge. April 27, 2018. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315159591-14.

  • Craver, Carl F., Donna Kwan, Chloe Steindam, and R. Shayna Rosenbaum. 2014. Individuals with episodic amnesia are not stuck in time. Neuropsychologia 57: 191–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, Felipe 2014. Is memory for remembering? Recollection as a form of episodic hypothetical thinking. Synthese 191 (2): 155–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, Felipe and Gessel, Bryce S. 2016. "Time is not of the Essence." in K.Michaelian, S.B. Klein, and K.K.Szpunar (Eds.) Seeing the Future. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 153-179.

  • Debus, Dorothea. 2014. ‘Mental time travel’: Remembering the past, imagining the future, and the particularity of events. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5 (3): 333–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deese, J. 1959. On the prediction of occurrence of particular verbal intrusions in immediate recall. Journal of Experimental Psychology 58: 17–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel Clement. 1989. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT pres

  • Dokic, Jérôme. 2014. Feeling the past: A two-tiered account of episodic memory. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5 (3): 413–426. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0183-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebbinghaus, H. 1885. Memory: A contribution to experimental psychology. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fivush, Robyn. 2011. The development of autobiographical memory. Annual Review of Psychology 62: 559–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harley, Keryn, and Elaine Reese. 1999. Origins of autobiographical memory. Developmental Psychology 35 (5): 1338–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hassabis, Demis, Dharshan Kumaran, Seralynne D. Vann, and Eleanor A. Maguire. 2007. Patients with hippocampal amnesia cannot imagine new experiences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 104 (5): 1726–1731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, J and Craver C. 2018. “Episodic Memory and the Witness Trump Card.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 41.

  • Hoerl, C. (2018). “Remembering Past Experiences: Episodic Memory, Semantic Memory, and the Epistemic Asymmetry.” In Michaelian, K., Debus, D., and Perrin, D., (eds.), New directions in the philosophy of memory (pages 313–328). Routledge.

  • Jablonka, Eva. 2017. “Collective Narratives, False Memories, and the Origins of Autobiographical Memory.” Biology & Philosophy 32 (6): 839–853.

  • Keven, Nazim. 2016. Events, narratives and memory. Synthese 193 (8): 2497–2517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keven, Nazim, Kurczek Jake, R. Shayna Rosenbaum, and Carl F. Craver. 2018. Narrative construction is intact in episodic amnesia. Neuropsychologia 110: 104–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurby, Christopher A., and Jeffrey M. Zacks. 2008. Segmentation in the perception and memory of events. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12 (2): 72–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kwan, Donna, Carl F. Craver, Leonard Green, Joel Myerson, Pascal Boyer, and R. Shayna Rosenbaum. 2012. Future decision-making without episodic mental time travel. Hippocampus 22 (6): 1215–1219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kwan, Donna, Carl F. Craver, Leonard Green, Joel Myerson, and R. Shayna Rosenbaum. 2013. Dissociations in future thinking following hippocampal damage: Evidence from discounting and time perspective in episodic amnesia. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 142 (4): 1355–1369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, Elizabeth F., David G. Miller, and Helen J. Burns. 1978. Semantic integration of verbal information into a visual memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory 4 (1): 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, Elizabeth F., and John C. Palmer. 1974. Reconstruction of automobile destruction: An example of the interaction between language and memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 13 (5): 585–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, Elizabeth F., and Jacqueline E. Pickrell. 1995. The formation of false memories. Psychiatric Annals 25 (12): 720–725.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahr, Johannes, and Gergely Csibra. 2017. “Why do we remember? The communicative function of episodic memory.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1–93.

  • Malcolm, Norman. 1963. 1975, Knowledge and Certainty: Essays and Lectures. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Charles B., and Max Deutscher. 1966. “Remembering.” The Philosophical Review 75 (2): 161–196.

  • McCarroll, Christopher. 2018. Remembering from the outside: Personal memory and the perspectival mind. Oxford University Press.

  • Michaelian, Kourken, Perin, Denis, and Sant’Anna, André. Forthcoming. “Continuities and discontinuities between imagination and memory: The view from philosophy”.

  • Michaelian, Kourken 2016, “Against Discontinuism: Mental Time Travel and Our Knowledge of Past and Future Events”, in Michaelian, Klein, & Szpunar 2016d: 62–92. doi:https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190241537.003.0004

  • Nanay, Bence. 2015. Perceptual content and the content of mental imagery. Philosophical Studies 172 (7): 1723–1736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, Katherine, and Robyn Fivush. 2004. The emergence of autobiographical memory: A social cultural developmental theory. Psychological Review 111 (2): 486–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, Gualtiero, and Carl F. Craver. 2011. Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese 183: 283–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigden, Charles. 2010. Hume on is and ought. Palgrave MacMillan.

  • Reese, Elaine. 2002. Social factors in the development of autobiographical memory: The state of the art. Social Development 11 (1): 124–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reid, Thomas. 1785. Of memory. Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man: 107–112.

  • Robins, Sarah K. 2016a. Misremembering. Philosophical Psychology 29 (3): 432–447. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2015.1113245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robins. 2016b. Representing the past: Memory traces and the causal theory of memory. Philosophical Studies 173 (11): 2993–3013. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0647-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, Sarah K. 2019. “Confabulation and Constructive Memory.” Synthese 196 (6): 2135–2151.

  • Roediger, Henry L., Suparna Rajaram, and Kavitha Srinivas. 1990. Specifying criteria for postulating memory systems. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 608 (1): 572–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roediger, H.L., and K.B. McDermott. 1995. Creating false memories: Remembering words not presented in lists. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 24 (4): 803–814.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, R. Shayna, Stefan Köhler, Daniel L. Schacter, Morris Moscovitch, Robyn Westmacott, Sandra E. Black, Fuqiang Gao, and Endel Tulving. 2005. The case of KC: Contributions of a memory-impaired person to memory theory. Neuropsychologia 43 (7): 989–1021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Restall, Greg, and Gillian Russell. 2010. “Barriers to Implication.” PIGDEN, C. Hume and ‘Is’ and ‘Ought’: New Essays. Rochester: Rochester University Press, No Prelo. 17p.

  • Russell, Gillian. 2010. “In Defence of Hume’s Law.” Hume, is, and ought: New essays. Charles Pigden, ed. Rochester University Press.

  • Sant’Anna, André. 2018. The hybrid contents of memory. Synthese, 1–28.

  • Schacter, Daniel L., and Donna Rose Addis. 2007. The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 362 (1481): 773–786. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2007.2087.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, Daniel L., Donna Rose Addis, Demis Hassabis, Victoria C. Martin, R. Nathan Spreng, and Karl K. Szpunar. 2012. The future of memory: Remembering, imagining, and the brain. Neuron 76 (4): 677–694. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2012.11.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, Kenneth F. 1993. Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. University of Chicago press.

  • Sellars, Wilfrid. 1956. Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1 (19): 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, Sydney. 1970. Persons and their pasts. American Philosophical Quarterly 7 (4): 269–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, Thomas, and Michael C. Corballis. 2007. The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (3): 299–313. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X07001975.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, Michael. 2014. A natural history of human thinking. Harvard University Press.

  • Tomasello, Michael. 2016. A natural history of human morality. Harvard University Press.

  • Tulving, Endel. 1983. Elements of episodic memory Oxford Univ. Oxford: Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargha-Khadem, Faraneh, David G. Gadian, Kate E. Watkins, Alan Connelly, Wim Van Paesschen, and Mortimer Mishkin. 1997. Differential effects of early hippocampal pathology on episodic and semantic memory. Science 277 (5324): 376–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carl F. Craver.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Craver, C.F. Remembering: Epistemic and Empirical. Rev.Phil.Psych. 11, 261–281 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00469-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00469-7

Navigation