Skip to main content
Log in

What Do False-Belief Tests Show?

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a (2018) paper published in Psychological Review, Tyler Burge has offered a unified non-mentalistic account of a wide range of social cognitive developmental findings. His proposal is that far from attributing mental states (e.g. beliefs), young children attribute to humans the same kind of internal generic states of sensory registration that biologists attribute to e.g. snails and ticks. Burge’s proposal deserves close attention: it is especially challenging because it departs from both the mentalistic and all the non-mentalistic accounts of the data so far. Moreover Burge has been one of the leading philosophers of mind of the past 40 years and some of his writings on the objectivity of perception display a deep understanding of the relevance of science for sharpening our understanding of the mind. After taking a close look at the developmental evidence, in particular at false-belief studies, I argue that Burge’s (Psychological Review, 125(3), 409–434, 2018) account faces severe obstacles. To give one telling example: if young children can only attribute to others sensory registrations, then it is hard to explain the evidence showing that they respond differently to an agent’s ignorance and to her false belief.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is reliable evidence that most 4,5 year-olds succeed on verbal false-belief tasks about an object’s location (cf. Wellman et al. 2001).

  2. As Bloom and German (2000) were the first to argue, the capacity for false-belief attribution cannot be sufficient for success on verbal false-belief tasks, because success also requires understanding the question asked by the experimenter. If they are right, then conversely failure on verbal false-belief tasks does not demonstrate the inability to attribute false beliefs to others.

  3. Some philosophers also endorse this position, cf. Carruthers (2013).

  4. Fabricius et al. (2010) have reported an intriguing pattern whereby most of the children (between 5 and 6 years of age), who succeed on verbal false-belief tasks about an object’s location, oddly fail on verbal true-belief tasks. They take these findings as evidence that these children cannot attribute genuine beliefs to others. In these true-belief tasks about an object’s location, the agent’s belief was true, but the agent did not know the object’s location in the philosophical epistemological sense of ‘know’, because before being placed back where the agent had put it before leaving the scene, the toy was temporarily displaced in the agent’s absence (cf. Oktay-Gür and Rakoczy 2017 for detailed discussion and for a pragmatic account of the failures in true-belief conditions). Burge does not discuss these findings which might lend support to his own point of view.

  5. Following his (2010) book, Burge (2018, p. 410) uses “attribution” in an unusually liberal way (at least among psychologists): “Not only individuals, but states, attribute things. Perceptual states attribute properties and relations to particular entities.”

  6. According to Burge’s anti-individualist standpoint, the contents of an individual’s perceptual representations depend on the individual’s non-social environment. In earlier work, Burge (1979) has also argued for antiindividualism (also called ‘social externalism’) with respect to an individual’s beliefs and other propositional attitudes by highlighting the contribution of the individual’s social environment (what members of her community think and say) to the contents of her beliefs and other mental states.

  7. Granting Burge his thesis that non-mental states lack representational functions, a deep question is: what gives mental states their representational functions? Burge seems to think that mental states do not derive their representational functions from evolution by natural selection. One alternative possibility highlighted by Dretske (1988), but not, so far as I can see, by Burge is that the representational functions of mental states rests on ontogenetic learning.

  8. I’ll ignore conscious states, which are irrelevant to the present discussion.

  9. Burge’s assumption here seems to be that sensory retention in the absence of a target can be construed as a non-mental counterpart to a mental state of believing or remembering.

  10. Knudsen and Liszkowski (2012) also rule out the possibility that infants attributed ignorance, rather than false belief, to the agent.

  11. Further significant evidence that toddlers (and even infants) construe differently an agent’s state of ignorance from an agent’s false belief comes from He et al. (2011) and Knudsen and Liszkowski (2012).

  12. The aspectuality of beliefs explains the intensionality (or referential opacity) of belief-attributions, exhibited by the fact that replacement of ‘Cicero’ by the coreferential name ‘Tully’ does not preserve the truth of the ascription ‘Mara believes that Cicero was a Roman orator’.

  13. Unlike false-belief tests about an object’s location, false-belief tests about object-identity have recently been called “aspectual” studies (cf. Rakoczy et al. 2015).

  14. Cf. Rakoczy, Fizke, Bergfeld, & Schwarz (2015) and Rakoczy (2016) for extended discussion. Burge himself discusses a study involving a toy figure first called Peter and casually dressed, then introduced as “the fire-fighter” and wearing a fire-fighter uniform that makes him look unrecognizably different from when he is casually dressed.

  15. Findings based on the false-belief condition of Scott and Baillargeon’s (2009) penguin study (discussed in section 3) can be taken to show that 18-month-olds attribute to the agent the false belief that the assembled two-piece penguin in the transparent box is the one-piece penguin. Buttelmann et al. (2015) provide evidence that most 18-month-olds give a rock, not a sponge, to an agent who is unsuccessfully trying to reach for a sponge that deceptively looks like a rock and which the agent falsely believes to be a rock.

  16. In other words, I will bracket any doubt as to whether a state of sensory retention is a genuine non-mental counterpart to mental states of believing or remembering.

  17. It is not clear, as I have argued in section 3, whether Burge thinks that the distinction between intention and desire (two mental states) can be mapped onto an equivalent distinction between a pair of generic non-mental internal conative states.

  18. Cf. Sober (1998) for extended discussion of this issue in evolutionary theorizing.

References

  • Apperly, I. & Robinson, E. 1998. Children’s mental representation of referential relations. Cognition 67, 287–309.

  • Apperly, I. & Robinson, E. 2003. When can children handle referential opacity? Evidence for systematic var- iation in 5- and 6-year-old children’s reasoning about beliefs and belief reports. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 85, 297–311.

  • Apperly, I., and S. Butterfill. 2009. Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belieflike states? Psychological Review 116 (4): 953–970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., R. Scott, and Z. He. 2010. False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14: 110–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P., and T. German. 2000. Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind. Cognition 77: B25–B31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 1979. Individualism and the mental. In Midwest studies in philosophy, ed. P. French, Theodore E. Uehling Jr., and H.K. Wettstein, vol. IV. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 2010. Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 2014. Perception: Where mind begins. Philosophy 89: 385–403.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 2018. Do infants attribute mental states? Psychological Review 125 (3): 409–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, D., M. Carpenter, and M. Tomasello. 2009. Eighteen-month-old infants show false belief understanding in an active helping paradigm. Cognition 112: 337–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, F., J. Suhrke, and D. Buttelmann. 2015. What you get is what you believe: Eighteen-month-olds demonstrate belief understanding in an unexpected-identity task. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 131: 94–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S., and I. Apperly. 2013. How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind & Language 28: 606–637.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. 2009. The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2013. Mindreading in infancy. Mind & Language 28: 141–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (manuscript) Representing the mental as such in infancy.

  • Davidson, D. 1982. Rational animals. In Davidson, D. (2001) subjective, intersubjective, objective: Philosophical essays, vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining behavior. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabricius, W.V., T.W. Boyer, A.A. Weimer, and K. Carroll. 2010. True or false: Do 5-year-olds understand beliefs? Developmental Psychology 46 (6): 1402–1416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1892/1952. On sense and reference. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Frege by Max Black and Peter Geach. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergely, G., and G. Csibra. 2003. Teleological reasoning in infancy: The naive theory of rational action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7: 287–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., & Tomasello, M. 2000. Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour 59(4), 771–785.

  • Hare, B., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. 2001. Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know? Animal Behaviour 61(1), 139–151.

  • He, Z., M. Bolz, and R. Baillargeon. 2011. False-belief understanding in 2.5-year-olds: Evidence from violation-of-expectation change-of-location and unexpected-contents tasks. Developmental Science 14 (2): 292–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F., and M. Simmel. 1944. An experimental study of apparent behavior. American Journal of Psychology 57: 243–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. 2014a. False belief in infancy: A fresh look. Developmental Science 17: 647–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. 2014b. Submentalizing: I am not really reading your mind. Perspectives on Psychological Science 9: 131–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyde, D.C., M.A. Aparicio Betancourt, and C.E. Simon. 2015. Human temporal-parietal junction spontaneously tracks others’ beliefs: A functional near-infrared spectroscopy study. Human Brain Mapping 36: 4831–4846.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyde, D.C., C.E. Simon, F. Ting, and J. Nikolaeva. 2018. Functional organization of the temporal-parietal junction for theory of mind in preverbal infants: A near-infrared spectroscopy study. Journal of Neuroscience 38 (18): 4264–4274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knudsen, B., and U. Liszkowski. 2012. 18-month-olds predict specific action mistakes through attribution of false belief, not ignorance, and intervene accordingly. Infancy 17 (6): 672–691.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kovács, A., E. Téglás, and A. Endress. 2010. The social sense: Susceptibility to others’ beliefs in human infants and adults. Science 330: 1830–1834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. 1994. ToMM, ToBY and agency: Core architecture and domain specificity. In Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in cognition and culture, ed. L. Hirschfeld and S. Gelman. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Y. 2010. Do 8-month-old infants consider situational constraints when interpreting others’ gaze as goal-directed action? Infancy 15 (4): 392–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Y. 2011. Three-month-old infants attribute goals to a non-human agent. Developmental Science 14: 453–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Y., and R. Baillargeon. 2005. Can a self-propelled box have a goal? Psychological reasoning in 5-month-old infants. Psychological Science 16: 601–608.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melis, A., J. Call, and M. Tomasello. 2006. Chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) conceal visual and auditory information from others. Journal of Comparative Psychology 120: 154–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.G. 2004. The varieties of meaning. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. Lloyd. 1894. An introduction to comparative psychology. London: Walter Scott.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oktay-Gür, N. & Rakoczy, H. 2017. Children’s difficulty with true belief tasks: Competence deficit or performance problem? Cognition 166, 28-41.

  • Onishi, K., and R. Baillargeon. 2005. Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science 308: 255–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D., and D. Povinelli. 2007. On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a ‘theory of mind’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 362: 731–744.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., and J. Roessler. 2012. From infants’ to children’s appreciation of belief. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 16 (10): 519–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., and T. Ruffman. 2005. Infants’ insight into the mind: How deep? Science 308: 314–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D., and T. Eddy. 1996. What chimpanzees know about seeing. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 61 (3): 1–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D.J., and J. Vonk. 2004. We don’t need a microscope to explore the Chimpanzee’s mind. Mind and Language 19: 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rakoczy, H., D. Bergfeld, I. Schwartz, and E. Fizke. 2015. Explicit theory of mind is even more unified than previously assumed: Belief ascription and understanding aspectuality emerge together in development. Child Development 86 (2): 485–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R., and R. Baillargeon. 2009. Which penguin is this? Attributing false beliefs about object identity at 18 months. Child Development 80: 1172–1196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1998. Morgan’s canon. In The evolution of mind, ed. D. Dellarosa Cummins and C. Allen, 224–242. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 2016a. Ockham’s razors: A user’s manual. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 2016b. Replies to Kristin Andrews’s, Gordon Belot’s, and Patrick Forber’s reviews. Metascience 25: 393–403.

    Google Scholar 

  • Song, H., and R. Baillargeon. 2008. Infants’ reasoning about others’ false perceptions. Developmental Psychology 44: 1789–1795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. 1988. Where perceiving ends and thinking begins: The apprehension of objects in infancy. In Perceptual development in infancy, the Minnesota Symposia on child psychology, ed. A. Yonas, vol. 20. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., and J. Call. 2006. Do chimpanzees know what others see—or only what they are looking at? In Rational animals, ed. S. Hurley and M. Nudds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H.M., Cross, D. and Watson, J. 2001. Meta-analysis of theory of mind devel- opment: the truth about false belief. Child Development 72, 655–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., and J. Perner. 1983. Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition 13: 103–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, A. 1998. Infants selectively code the goal object of an actor’s reach. Cognition 69: 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to the Editor and to four anonymous reviewers, to Andreas Falck, George Galfalvi, Gyuri Gergely and Dan Sperber, for their insightful comments and criticisms on earlier versions of this paper, and also to Ned Block for conversations on the topic of this paper. I gratefully acknowledge support from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union Seventh Programme (FP/2007-2013)/ERC Grant 609819.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre Jacob.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jacob, P. What Do False-Belief Tests Show?. Rev.Phil.Psych. 11, 1–20 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00442-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00442-z

Navigation