Skip to main content
Log in

Memory: Irreducible, Basic, and Primary Source of Knowledge

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue against preservationism, the epistemic claim that memories can at most preserve knowledge generated by other basic types of sources. I show how memories can and do generate knowledge that is irreducible to other basic sources of knowledge. In some epistemic contexts, memories are primary basic sources of knowledge; they can generate knowledge by themselves or with trivial assistance from other types of basic sources of knowledge. I outline an ontology of information transmission from events to memory as an alternative to causal theories of memory. I derive from information theory a concept of reliability of memories as the ratio of retrieved information to transmitted information. I distinguish the generation of knowledge from reliable memories from its generation from unreliable memories. Reliable memories can generate new knowledge by forming together narratives and via colligation. Coherent, even unreliable, memories can generate knowledge if they are epistemically independent of each other and the prior probability of the knowledge they generate is sufficiently low or high. Ascertaining the epistemic independence of memories and eliminating possible confounders may be achieved through the generation of knowledge from independent memories in different minds, when memories are primary basic sources of knowledge and the testimonies that report them are trivial.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Preservationism may accept testimony as a fourth basic source of knowledge. However, I am not familiar with a philosopher who held a preservationist view of memory and considered testimony an irreducible basic source of knowledge.

  2. Michaelian (2016, 40) argues that it is impossible to evaluate the reliabilities of processes that generate beliefs from memory because they would have to rely on memory itself for evaluating which beliefs are true. Michaelian overstates his case since memory does not have to epistemically bootstrap itself when it is possible to measure the coherence, or what Lewis (1946) called “congruence,” of beliefs generated by types of memory with knowledge generated by other basic sources of knowledge. But since it is impossible to measure the frequency of true beliefs among all the beliefs that types of memory have generated, it would be necessary to measure the frequency of true beliefs in samples of them. It may be difficult in avoid unintentional sampling biases and errors.

  3. Bernecker (2010, 99) dismisses such cases under the rubric of “inattentive remembering.” He claims that despite the absence of belief at t1 when the memory is formed, there is a “representation” at t1 that has identical epistemic status to that of the belief that would be formed from memory. “What distinguishes S’s propositional attitude at t1 from his propositional attitude at t2 is awareness or conceptualization but not justification.” However, there is no reason to believe that when information flows through the senses to memory, bypassing consciousness, it creates a representation, let alone a justified one. Information is encoded in memory and later decoded. When it is encoded, it does not have to constitute a justified representation and when it is decoded it can serve as justification for new knowledge or belief. In between, memory in its encoded latent state is not a representation.

  4. A defeater can be normative, if it implies that the belief ought to be defeated, or a psychological state of mind that prevents the agent from knowing, like a trauma. (Lackey 2008, 44–5) More orthodox distinctions are between “external” propositional or factual defeaters, and “internal” states of mind. (Cf. Grundmann 2011)

  5. In Dumas’ novel, abbé Faria contributes the empirical generalization that the handwriting of right-handed people who write with their left hand are similar and information about the Deputy who examined Dantès and his motivation for destroying evidence that could have exonerated him. I ignore this part of the plot because the rest is sufficient to make the epistemic point.

  6. I thank Sanford Goldberg for presenting me with this argument in our conversations after I presented a version of this paper at the European Epistemology Network Meeting in Paris in the summer of 2016.

  7. Ceteris paribus, the more information rich, e.g., detailed, are independent and coherent memories, the lower is the prior probability of the information they transmit and hence the higher is their posterior probability. This creates a psychological association between degree of detail of memory and reliability. However, the reliabilities of individual memories or testimonies are independent of their richness of detail. Fantasized memories and fabricated testimonies (like the email you received from Nigeria about a financial transaction…) can be very detailed. The degree of detail decreases the prior probability and hence is significant if and only if there are multiple coherent and independent memories or testimonies.

    Experimental psychologists attempt to understand how “metamemory” monitors the reliabilities of memories through “source monitoring.” When we reconstruct memories, we check for “tags” in the traces about their origins to authenticate them. The rules that regulate this unconscious process that accompanies memory construction are fallible but should be statistically reliable. The degree of detail seems to be one of these “tags.” (Michaelian 2011, 329 following Mitchell and Johnson 2000) Such tags assigned to individual memories, as distinct from multiple, independent, and coherent memories are not reliable evaluators of reliability. Here, epistemology should be “denaturalized” to normatively distinguish rational from actual-psychological evaluation of reliability, as behavioral economics demonstrated the gap between rational and actual economic behavior.

  8. Pr(H|E&B) = [Pr(E|H&B)xPr(H|B)]:Pr(E|B)

    Pr stands for the probability of...

    H stands for any hypothesis, which in our case means what the memories assert, the winning number in the lottery.

    E stands for evidence, which in our case means the coherent and independent memories.

    B stands for background knowledge that assists in determining the variables (including ranges of possible probabilities).

    The vertical line | should be read as “given,” for example, Pr(H|E&B) means the probability of a hypothesis given evidence and background information.

    Pr(H|B) is the prior probability of a particular hypothesis given background knowledge, for example, the odds of a winning a lottery.

    Pr(E|H&B) expresses the likelihood of the evidence given the hypothesis in question in conjunction with background knowledge, the reliability of the memories in this context. For example, given the winning number in the lottery, how likely it is that Rene remembers it forty years later?

    Pr(E|B) expresses the expectedness, the probability of the evidence given background information, whether or not the hypothesis is true. Another way of putting it formally is:

    Pr(E|B) = [Pr(E|H&B) x Pr(H|B)] + [Pr(E|-H&B) x Pr(−H|B)].

    The posterior probability of the hypothesis given the evidence and background information, Pr(H|E&B), is the ratio of the likelihood of the evidence (coherent independent memories) given the hypothesis and its prior probability, to the expectedness of the evidence whether or not the hypothesis is true. Imagine all the possible worlds where the memories in question occur, and then ask in which fraction of these worlds the hypothesis is the case.

  9. Bovens and Hartmann (2003, 115–123) applied Bayesian probability to the epistemology of testimony, but it is just as applicable to any independent epistemic sources such as memories. They modelled the effects of prior probabilities on posterior probabilities in a Cartesian space, given multiple independent epistemic sources: The curve is U shaped. As the prior probabilities increase, the posterior probabilities decrease, up to a point where high priors begin to determine the posterior probabilities that rise in tandem with them. The more unreliable are the memories the deeper is the “valley” in the U-shaped curve between the high posterior probabilities that result from very low and very high prior probabilities.

References

  • Ambrogi Lorenzini, C.G., E. Baldi, C. Bucherelli, B. Sacchetti, and G. Tassoni. 1999. Neural topography and chronology of memory consolidation: A review of functional inactivation findings. Neurobiology of Learning and Memory 71: 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ankersmit, F.R. 1983. Narrative logic: A semantic analysis of the Historian’s language. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ankersmit, F.R. 2008. Narrative and interpretation. In Companion to the Philosophy of history and historiography, ed. Aviezer Tucker, 199–208. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 1997. The place of testimony in the fabric of knowledge and justification. American Philosophical Quarterly 34: 405–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 2002. The sources of knowledge. In The Oxford handbook of epistemology, ed. P. Moser, 71–94. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ball, Karyn. 2013. Hayden White’s hope, or the politics of prefiguration. In Philosophy of history after Hayden white, ed. Robert Doran, 89–108. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernecker, Sven. 2010. Memory: A philosophical study. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, Luc, and Stephan Hartmann. 2003. Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, David. 1986. Time, narrative and history. Bloomington IN: University of Indiana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred I. 1981. Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumas, Alexandre. 1864. Le Comte de Monte Cristo. Paris: M. Lévy frères.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael. 1994. Testimony and Memory. In Knowing from Words: Western And Indian Philosophical Analysis of Understanding and Testimony, ed. Bimal Krishna Matilal and Arindam Chakrabarti, 251–272. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gooch, George Peabody. 1959. History and historians in the nineteenth century. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grundmann, Thomas. 2011. Defeasibility Theory. In The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, ed. Sven Bernecker and Duncan Pritchard, 156–166. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, Nick. 2008. Explanatory genealogies and historical testimony. Episteme 5: 160–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kenyon, Tim. 2016. Oral history and the epistemology of testimony. Social Epistemology 30: 45–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, Jennifer. 2007. Why memory really is a generative epistemic source: A reply to Senor. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 209–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, Jennifer. 2008. Learning from words: Testimony as a source of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, Jennifer. 2011. Testimonial Knowledge. In The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, ed. Sven Bernecker and Duncan Pritchard, 316–325. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, Pierre-Simon. 1840. Essai philosophique sur les probabilités, 6 th Eds. Paris: Bachelier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C.I. 1946. An analysis of knowledge and valuation. La Salle IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCullagh, C. Behan. 2008. Colligation. In Companion to the Philosophy of history and historiography, ed. Aviezer Tucker, 152–161. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2011. Generative memory. Philosophical Psychology 24: 323–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2016. Mental time travel: Episodic memory and our knowledge of the personal past. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, K.J., and M.K. Johnson. 2000. Source monitoring: Attributing mental experiences. In Oxford handbook of memory, ed. E. Tulving and F.I.M. Craik, 175–195. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, Erik J. 2005. Against coherence: Truth, probability, and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E.J., and T. Shogenji. 2004. Can we trust our memories? C. I. Lewis’s coherence argument. Synthese 142: 21–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, Alvin. 1993. Warrant and proper function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 1983-1985. Temps et récit, Vols I-III. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robins, Sarah. 2016. Representing the past: Memory traces and the causal theory of memory. Philosophical Studies 173: 2993–3013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D.L., and D.R. Addis. 2007. The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 362: 773–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Senor, Thomas D. 2007. Preserving Preservationism: A reply to Lackey. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 199–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Squire, L.R., and S. Zola-Morgan. 1991. The medial temporal lobe memory system. Science 253: 1380–1386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1994. Knowing from Words. In Knowing from Words: Western And Indian Philosophical Analysis of Understanding and Testimony, ed. Bimal Krishna Matilal and Arindam Chakrabarti, 23–28. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 1998. Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, Aviezer. 2004. Our knowledge of the past: A Philosophy of historiography. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, Aviezer. 2016. The generation of knowledge from multiple testimonies. Social Epistemology 30: 251–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, W.H. 1960. Philosophy of history: An introduction. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, Timothy. 2007. On being justified in One's head. In Rationality and the good: Critical essays on the ethics and epistemology of Robert Audi, ed. M. Timmons, J. Greco, and A.R. Mele, 106–122. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zaragoza, M.S., and K.J. Mitchell. 1996. Repeated exposure to suggestion and the creation of false memories. Psychological Science 7: 294–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aviezer Tucker.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tucker, A. Memory: Irreducible, Basic, and Primary Source of Knowledge. Rev.Phil.Psych. 9, 1–16 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0336-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0336-5

Navigation