Review of Philosophy and Psychology

, Volume 6, Issue 4, pp 865–879 | Cite as

Relations Between Agency and Ownership in the Case of Schizophrenic Thought Insertion and Delusions of Control

Article

Abstract

This article addresses questions about the sense of agency and its distinction from the sense of ownership in the context of understanding schizophrenic thought insertion. In contrast to “standard” approaches that identify problems with the sense of agency as central to thought insertion, two recent proposals argue that it is more correct to think that the problem concerns the subject’s sense of ownership. This view involves a “more demanding” concept of the sense of ownership that, I will argue, ultimately depends on the sense of agency. In this regard, the sense of agency still appears to be the originating problem.

References

  1. Albahari, M. 2006. Analytic Buddhism: The two-tiered illusion of self. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Balslev, D., J. Cole, and R.C. Miall. 2007. Proprioception contributes to the sense of agency during visual observation of hand movements: evidence from temporal judgments of action. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19(9): 1535–1541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Benes, F.M. 2000. Emerging principles of altered neural circuitry in schizophrenia. Brain Research Reviews 31: 251–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bermúdez, J.L. 2011. Bodily awareness and self-consciousness. In The Oxford handbook of the self, ed. S. Gallagher, 157–179. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Billon, A. 2013. Does consciousness entail subjectivity? The puzzle of thought insertion. Philosophical Psychology 26(2): 291–314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Billon, A., and U. Kriegel. 2014. Jaspers’ dilemma: The psychopathological challenge to subjectivity theories of consciousness. In Disturbed consciousness, ed. R. Gennaro. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bleuler, E. 1950. Dementia praecox or the group of schizophrenias. Oxford: International Universities Press.Google Scholar
  8. Bortolotti, L. 2010. Delusions and other irrational beliefs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Bortolotti, L., and M. Broome. 2009. A role for ownership and authorship in the analysis of thought insertion. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(2): 205–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Bratman, M.E. 1987. Intention, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Campbell, J. 1999. Schizophrenia, the space of reasons and thinking as a motor process. The Monist 82(4): 609–625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Campbell, J. 2002. The ownership of thoughts. Philosophy Psychology and Psychiatry 9(1): 35–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Chaminade, T., and J. Decety. 2002. Leader or follower? Involvement of the inferior parietal lobule in agency. Neuroreport 13(1528): 1975–1978.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Desmurget, M., K.T. Reilly, N. Richard, et al. 2009. Movement intention after parietal cortex stimulation in humans. Science 324: 811–813.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Farrer, C., and C.D. Frith. 2002. Experiencing oneself vs. another person as being the cause of an action: the neural correlates of the experience of agency. NeuroImage 15: 596–603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Farrer, C., N. Franck, N. Georgieff, et al. 2003. Modulating the experience of agency: a positron emission tomography study. NeuroImage 18: 324–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Ford, J., B. Roach, W. Faustman, et al. 2007. Synch before you speak: auditory hallucinations in schizophrenia. American Journal of Psychiatry 164(3): 458–466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Frankfurt, H.G. 1988. The importance of what we care about: Philosophical essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Friston, K.J., and C.D. Frith. 1995. Schizophrenia: a disconnection syndrome? Clinical Neuroscience 3: 89–97.Google Scholar
  20. Frith, C.D. 1992. The cognitive neuropsychology of Schizophrenia. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  21. Frith, C.D., S. Blakemore, and D. Wolpert. 2000. Abnormalities in the awareness and control of action. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London 355: 1771–1788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Gallagher, S. 2000. Philosophical conceptions of the self: implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Science 4(1): 14–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Gallagher, S. 2004. Neurocognitive models of schizophrenia: a neurophenomenological critique. Psychopathology 37: 8–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Gallagher, S. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Gallagher, S. (2007). Sense of agency and higher-order cognition: levels of explanation for schizophrenia. Cognitive Semiotics, 0, 32–48.Google Scholar
  26. Gallagher, S. 2011. In Time in action. Oxford handbook on time, ed. C. Callender, 419–37. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Gallagher, S. 2012. Multiple aspects of agency. New Ideas in Psychology 30: 15–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Gallagher, S., and A. Marcel. 1999. The self in contextualized action. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6(4): 4–30.Google Scholar
  29. Gallagher, S., and F. Varela. 2003. Redrawing the map and resetting the time: phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29: 93–132.Google Scholar
  30. Gallagher, S. and Zahavi, D. (2010). Phenomenological approaches to self-consciousness. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/self-consciousness-phenomenological/.
  31. Georgieff, N., and M. Jeannerod. 1998. Beyond consciousness of external events: a ‘who’ system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 7: 465–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Gold, I., and J. Hohwy. 2000. Rationality and schizophrenic delusion. In Pathologies of belief, ed. M. Coltheart and M. Davies, 145–165. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  33. Graham, G., and G.L. Stephens. 1994. Mind and mine. In Philosophical psychopathology, ed. G. Graham and G.L. Stephens, 91–109. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  34. Graybiel, M.S. 1997. The basal ganglia and cognitive pattern generators. Schizophrenia Bulletin 23: 459–469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Grünbaum, T. 2010. Action and agency. In Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science, ed. S. Gallagher and D. Schmicking, 337–354. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Haggard, P., and M. Eimer. 1999. On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Experimental Brain Research 126: 128–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Haggard, P., and E. Magno. 1999. Localising awareness of action with transcranial magnetic stimulation. Experimental Brain Research 127: 102–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Jeannerod, M. 2003. The mechanism of self-recognition in humans. Behavioural Brain Research 142(1): 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Kalckert, A., & Ehrsson, H. H. (2012). Moving a rubber hand that feels like your own: a dissociation of ownership and agency. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 6.Google Scholar
  40. Lane, T. 2014. Self, belonging, and conscious experience: A critique of subjectivity theories of consciousness. In Disturbed consciousness: New essays on psychopathology and theories of consciousness, ed. R. Gennaro. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  41. Langland-Hassan, P. 2008. Fractured phenomenologies: thought insertion, inner speech, and the puzzle of extraneity. Mind & Language 23(4): 369–401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Marcel, A. 2003. The sense of agency: Awareness and ownership of action. In Agency and awareness, ed. J. Roessler and N. Eilan, 48–93. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  43. McKay, R., R. Langdon, and M. Coltheart. 2005. “Sleights of mind”: delusions, defences, and self-deception. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry 10(4): 305–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Pacherie, E. 2006. Towards a dynamic theory of intentions. In Does consciousness cause behavior? An investigation of the nature of volition, ed. S. Pockett, W.P. Banks, and S. Gallagher, 145–167. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Pacherie, E. (2007). The sense of control and the sense of agency. Psyche, 13(1). http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/.
  46. Roessler, J. 2013. Thought insertion, self-awareness, and rationality. In The Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry, ed. K.W.M. Fulford et al., 658–72. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Sass, L., and J. Parnas. 2003. Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin 29(3): 427–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Seeger, M. 2014. Authorship of thoughts in thought insertion: what is it for a thought to be one’s own? Philosophical Psychology. doi:10.1080/09515089.2014.942897.Google Scholar
  49. Singh, J.R., T. Knight, N. Rosenlicht, et al. 1992. Abnormal premovement brain potentials in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research 8: 31–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Spencer, K.M., P.G. Nestor, M.A. Niznikiewicz, et al. 2003. Abnormal neural synchrony in schizophrenia. The Journal of Neuroscience 23(19): 7407–7411.Google Scholar
  51. Startup, M. 1996. Insight and cognitive deficits in schizophrenia: evidence for a curvilinear relationship. Psychological Medicine 26(6): 1277–1282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Stephan, K. E., Friston, K. J., & Frith, C. D. (2009). Dysconnection in schizophrenia: from abnormal synaptic plasticity to failures of self-monitoring. Schizophrenia Bulletin, sbn176.Google Scholar
  53. Stephens, G.L., and G. Graham. 2000. When self-consciousness breaks: Alien voices and inserted thoughts. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  54. Synofzik, M., G. Vosgerau, and A. Newen. 2008. Beyond the comparator model: a multifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness and Cognition 17(1): 219–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Tsakiris, M., and P. Haggard. 2005. Experimenting with the acting self. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3/4): 387–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Uhlhaas, P.J., and W. Singer. 2010. Abnormal neural oscillations and synchrony in schizophrenia. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11(2): 100–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Varela, F.J., J.-P. Lachaux, E. Rodriguez, et al. 2001. The brainweb: phase synchronization and large-scale integration. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 2: 229–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Vosgerau, G., and A. Newen. 2007. Thoughts, motor actions, and the self. Mind & Language 22(1): 22–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of MemphisMemphisUSA
  2. 2.School of HumanitiesUniversity of HertfordshireHertfordshireUK
  3. 3.Faculty of Law, Humanities and the ArtsUniversity of WollongongWollongongAustralia

Personalised recommendations