Skip to main content
Log in

Pluralism on Artefact Categories: A Philosophical Defence

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we use our work in the philosophy of technology to formulate a pluralist view on artefact categories and categorisation principles, as studied in cognitive science. We argue, on the basis of classifications derived by philosophical reconstruction, that artefacts can be clustered in more than one way, and that each clustering may be taken as defining psychological artefact categories. We contrast this pluralism with essentialism and super-minimalism on artefact categories and we argue that pluralism is coherent with experimental results regarding the context-dependence of artefact categorisation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Strevens (2000) limits his minimalism to biological and chemical categories. He conjectures that artefact categorisation requires a different explanation, in terms of what he calls ‘teleokinds’ (see: http://strevens.org/research/concepts.shtml; accessed March 2013).

  2. To bring out the difference between what is under debate in cognitive science and what we derive from philosophy of technology, we specify how we use key terms in this paper. We refer to the cognitive act of grouping or differentiating artefacts as ‘(artefact) categorisation’; by contrast, we refer to our process of philosophical reconstruction as ‘classification’. ‘Category’ refers to a product of the cognitive act of categorisation, guided (perhaps) by one or more ‘principles of categorisation’; ‘class’ refers to the products of our philosophical reconstruction. ‘Kind’, to introduce one more term, refers to the real groupings of entities, under debate in metaphysics. This paper defends a view on categories, based on work about classes. It is not concerned with kinds.

  3. See Malt and Sloman (2007: Section 2) for a review of the various options considered, as well as relevant debates and experimental studies.

  4. Inspired by Michael Bratman’s characterisation of plans as ‘intentions writ large’ (1987: 29).

  5. Interactions include physical manipulations (e.g., pressing, turning), remote causal interactions (e.g., accelerating space probes by means of Jupiter’s gravitational field), and observations (e.g., watching traffic lights).

  6. Simon (1996) holds a similarly liberal view, in which designing is primarily about devising actions.

  7. More elaborate action–theoretical characterisations of designing, product designing, manufacturing designing and making can be found in (Houkes and Vermaas 2009b, 2014).

  8. (Vermaas and Houkes 2006b; Houkes and Vermaas 2010).

  9. In (Houkes and Vermaas 2014) we have considered the possibility that one of the many elements of our classification systems may correspond to natural kinds, by exploring arguments that artefact kinds correspond to id made-product classes. This is not a return to Bloom’s psychological essentialism, but a project in metaphysics different to the current one of mapping our systems of classification onto psychological artefact categories.

  10. As noted before, Strevens, the principal advocate of minimalism, agrees, and limits his view to biological and chemical kinds. This does not, of course, undermine Sloman and Malt’s argument against a hypothetical minimalism about artefact categorisation.

  11. Bloom (2007) argues that essentialism is also compatible with the divergence between naming and artefact recognition, so compatibility with this divergence seems a minimal requirement for plausible views on artefact categorisation rather than a way to differentiate such views.

  12. To make the task less time-consuming, subjects were asked to sort all items into piles rather than give pairwise similarity judgements; and subjects were asked to sort by only two out of the three sorting principles.

  13. This resemblance is almost a prerequisite of the experimental set-up, because the morphed image has to resemble both types of item.

References

  • Ahn, W., C. Kalish, S.A. Gelman, D.L. Medin, C. Luhmann, S. Atran, J.D. Coley, and P. Shafto. 2001. Why essences are essential in the psychology of concepts. Cognition 82(1): 59–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. 1996. Intention, history, and artifact concepts. Cognition 60(1): 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. 1998. Theories of artifact categorization. Cognition 66(1): 87–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. 2007. More than words: A reply to Malt and Sloman. Cognition 105(3): 649–655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M.E. 1987. Intention, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A., and O. Dreier (eds.). 2006. Doing things with things: The design and use of everyday objects. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. 2007. On the place of artifacts in ontology. In Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence, 33–51. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franssen, M. 2006. The normativity of artefacts. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37(1): 42–57.

  • Franssen, M., P. Kroes, T.A.C. Reydon, and P. E. Vermaas. ed. 2014. Artefact kinds: Ontology and the human-made world. Synthese Library, vol. 365. Berlin: Springer.

  • Houkes, W., and P.E. Vermaas. 2004. Actions versus functions: A plea for an alternative metaphysics of artifacts. The Monist 87(1): 52–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W., and P.E. Vermaas. ed. 2009a. Artefacts in analytic metaphysics. Techné 13(2).

  • Houkes, W., and P.E. Vermaas. 2009. Contemporary engineering and the metaphysics of artefacts: Beyond the Artisan model. The Monist 92(3): 403–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W., and P.E. Vermaas. 2010. Technical functions: On the use and design of artefacts. Philosophy of Engineering and Technology 1. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Houkes, W., and P.E. Vermaas. 2014. On what is made: Instruments, products and natural kinds of artefacts. Forthcoming in Artefact kinds: Ontology and the human-made world, ed. M. Franssen, P. Kroes, T.A.C. Reydon, and P. E. Vermaas. Synthese Library, vol. 365. Berlin: Springer.

  • Hughes, J. 2009. An artifact is to use: An introduction to instrumental functions. Synthese 168:179–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. 2008. The designer fallacy and technological imagination. In Philosophy and design: From engineering to architecture, ed. P.E. Vermaas, P. Kroes, A. Light, and S.A. Moore, 51–59. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kroes, P. 2012. Technical artefacts: Creations of mind and matter. Philosophy of Engineering and Technology 6. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Malt, B.C., and S.A. Sloman. 2007. Artifact categorization: The good, the bad, and the ugly. In Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence, 85–123. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malt, B.C., S.A. Sloman, S. Gennari, M. Shi, and Y. Wang. 1999. Knowing versus naming: Similarity and the linguistic categorization of artifacts. Journal of Memory and Language 40(2): 230–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., and S. Laurence (eds.). 2007. Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1996. The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. ed. 2009. Philosophy and engineering. The Monist 92(3).

  • Sloman, S.A., and B.C. Malt. 2003. Artifacts are not ascribed essences, nor are they treated as belonging to kinds. Language & Cognitive Processes 18(5–6): 563–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, S.A., M.C. Harrison, and B.C. Malt. 2002. Recent exposure affects artifact naming. Memory & Cognition 30(5): 687–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2000. The essentialist aspect of naive theories. Cognition 74(2): 149–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2001. Only causation matters: Reply to Ahn Et Al. Cognition 82(1): 71–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. 2007. Artifacts and human concepts. In Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence, 52–73. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermaas, P.E., and W. Houkes. 2006a. Use plans and artefact functions: An intentionalist approach to artefacts and their use. In Doing things with things: The design and use of everyday objects, ed. A. Costall and O. Dreier, 29–48. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermaas, P.E., and W. Houkes. 2006b. Technical functions: A drawbridge between the intentional and structural natures of technical artefacts. Studies In History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37(1): 5–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Research by Wybo Houkes was made possible by the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wybo Houkes.

Additional information

Revised submission to the Review of Philosophy and Psychology special issue on artefact categorisation, guest-edited by Massimiliano Carrara and Daria Mingardo

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Houkes, W., Vermaas, P.E. Pluralism on Artefact Categories: A Philosophical Defence. Rev.Phil.Psych. 4, 543–557 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-013-0149-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-013-0149-0

Keywords

Navigation