Abstract
Knobe (Analysis 63:190-193, 2003a, Philosophical Psychology 16:309-324, 2003b, Analysis 64:181-187, 2004b) found that people are more likely to attribute intentionality to agents whose actions resulted in negative side-effects that to agents whose actions resulted in positive ones. Subsequent investigation has extended this result to a variety of other folk psychological attributions. The present article reports experimental findings that demonstrate an analogous effect for belief ascriptions. Participants were found to be more likely to ascribe belief, higher degrees of belief, higher degrees of rational belief, and dispositional belief to agents in central Knobe effect cases who bring about negative side-effects than to agents who bring about positive ones. These findings present a significant challenge to widely held views about the Knobe effect, since many explanations of it assume that agents in contrasting pairs of Knobe effect cases do not differ with respect to their beliefs. Participants were also found to be more confident that knowledge should be attributed than they were that belief or dispositional belief should be attributed. This finding strengthens the challenge that Myers-Schulz and Schwitzgebel (2013) have launched against the traditional view that knowledge entails belief.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Additional studies (e.g., Cova and Naar 2013) have uncovered a similar effect with means rather than side-effects.
Cf., e.g., Hindriks (2008); Knobe (2004a, 2006); Knobe and Burra (2006); Leslie et al. (2006); Doris et al. (2007); Knobe and Doris (2010); Nadelhoffer (2004a, b, 2006); Machery (2008); McCann (2005); Mele (2006); Mele and Cushman (2007); Cushman and Mele (2007); Pettit and Knobe (2009); Sverdlik (2004).
Italics did not appear in the research materials and are used here only for purposes of explanation.
Environment: Mann–Whitney U = 1843, p < 0.01, r = -0.25. Movies: U = 568.5, p < 0.01, r = -0.31. Sales: U = 919.5, p > 0.05, r = -0.02. Nazi: U = 651, p < 0.05, r = -0.23. All significance tests two-tailed. Pairwise tests of statistical significance were used instead of a two-way ANOVA because the differences between ENVIRONMENT, MOVIES, SALES, and NAZI render them separate pairs of cases more than different levels of a common independent variable.
The apparent size of a given Knobe effect has been shown to depend in part upon the kind of prompt question participants are asked. For example, Beebe and Jensen (2012, secs. 1–2) found small effect sizes when using 7-point Likert scales but large effect sizes when using forced-choice formats, even though other features of the experimental materials were held constant.
Environment: Mann–Whitney U = 221, p < 0.001, r = -0.71. Movies: t (55) = 2.81, p < 0.001, r = 0.35. Sales: t (49) = 2.12, p < 0.05, r = 0.29. Nazi: t (75) = 1.07, p > 0.05, r = 0.12. Independent samples t-tests were used for the latter three cases because the data distributions more closely approximate normal distributions.
Mean male response in positive conditions: 0.52. Mean female response in positive conditions: 0.24. Male negative mean: 0.92. Female negative mean: 0.38. F(1, 215) = 3.418, p = 0.066, partial η 2 = 0.016.
Of course, the information deleted from NAZI was not hindsight information in the same sense as in the other cases, but it was deleted for the sake of consistency.
Environment: Mann–Whitney U = 429.5, p < 0.001, r = -0.46. Movies: U = 428.5, p < 0.001, r = -0.42. Sales: U = 387, p < 0.001, r = -0.5. Nazi: U = 462.5, p < 0.001, r = -0.46.
Due to the large number of significant differences, no brackets with asterisks were used to indicate these differences in Fig. 4 in order to keep the graph from becoming too cluttered.
Environment: F(1, 67) = 6.542, p < 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.089. Movies: F(1, 72) = 1.150, p > 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.016. Sales: F(1, 71) = 6.933, p < 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.089. Nazi: F(1, 71) = 5.369, p < 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.070.
Environment: F(1, 67) = 50.801, p < 0.001, partial η 2 = 0.431. Movies: F (1, 72) = 18.220, p < 0.001, partial η 2 = 0.202. Sales: F(1, 71) = 0.822, p > 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.011. Nazi: F(1, 71) = 11.088, p < 0.01, partial η 2 = 0.135.
F(1, 71) = 4.910, p < 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.065
I did not represent significant differences from uniformity (i.e., an even 33.3 % split across all three categories), since such differences would not be theoretically meaningful.
Two-sample Kolmogorov-Smirnov D = 0.0588, p > 0.05.
The percentages in the first two groups also differed significantly from that of the third group, but since these differences are theoretically inconsequential, I did not represent them in Fig. 6.
Two-sample Kolmogorov-Smirnov D = 0.1690, p < 0.05.
F(1, 84) = 7.488, p < 0.01, partial η 2 = 0.082.
F(1, 87) = 1.526, p > 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.017.
Environment: F(1, 57) = 3.665, p = 0.061, partial η 2 = 0.060. Movies: F(1, 56) = 0.113, p > 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.002. Sales: F(1, 58) = 2.258, p > 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.037. Nazi F(1, 56) = 6.178, p < 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.099.
Due to the large number of significant differences, no brackets with asterisks were used to indicate these differences in Fig. 9 in order to keep the graph from becoming too cluttered.
Environment: F(1, 57) = 13.532, p < 0.01, partial η 2 = 0.192. Movies: F(1, 56) = 10.690, p < 0.01, partial η 2 = 0.160. Sales: F(1, 58) = 0.744, p > 0.05, partial η 2 = 0.013. Nazi F(1, 56) = 27.034, p < 0.01, partial η 2 = 0.153.
This difference, however, failed to reach statistical significance. Two-sample Kolmogorov-Smirnov D = 0.0818., p > 0.05.
Two-sample Kolmogorov-Smirnov D = 0.0684, p > 0.05.
References
Beebe, J.R., and W. Buckwalter. 2010. The epistemic side-effect effect. Mind & Language 25: 474–498.
Beebe, J.R., and M. Jensen. 2012. Surprising connections between knowledge and action: The robustness of the epistemic side-effect effect. Philosophical Psychology 25: 689–715.
Cova, F., and H. Naar. 2013. Side-effect effect without side effect: The pervasive impact of moral considerations on judgments of intentionality. Philosophical Psychology.
Cushman, F., and A. Mele. 2007. Intentional action: Two-and-a-half folk concepts? In Experimental Philosophy, ed. J. Knobe and S. Nichols, 171–188. New York: Oxford University Press.
Doris, J., J. Knobe, and R.L. Woolfolk. 2007. Variantism about responsibility. Philosophical Perspectives 21: 183–214.
Hindriks, F. 2008. Intentional action and the praise-blame asymmetry. The Philosophical Quarterly 58: 630–641.
Hsee, C.K. 1998. Less is better: When low-value options are valued more highly than high-value options. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 11: 107–121.
Knobe, J. 2003a. Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63: 190–193.
Knobe, J. 2003b. Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation. Philosophical Psychology 16: 309–324.
Knobe, J. 2004a. Folk psychology and folk morality: Response to critics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24: 270–279.
Knobe, J. 2004b. Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis 64: 181–187.
Knobe, J. 2006. The concept of intentional action: A case study in the uses of folk psychology. Philosophical Studies 130: 203–231.
Knobe, J. 2007. Reason explanation in folk psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31: 90–106.
Knobe, J. 2010. Person as scientist, person as moralist. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33: 315–329.
Knobe, J., and A. Burra. 2006. The folk concepts of intention and intentional action: A cross-cultural study. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6: 113–132.
Knobe, J., and J. Doris. 2010. Responsibility. In J. Doris and the Moral Psychology Research Group (Eds.), The Handbook of Moral Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 321-54.
Knobe, J., and G. Mendlow. 2004. The good, the bad and the blameworthy. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24: 252–258.
Lanteri, A. 2012. Three-and-a-half folk concepts of intentional action. Philosophical Studies 158: 17–30.
Leslie, A.M., J. Knobe, and A. Cohen. 2006. Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: Theory of mind and moral judgment. Psychological Science 17: 421–427.
Machery, E. 2008. The folk concept of intentional action: Philosophical and experimental issues. Mind & Language 23: 165–189.
McCann, H. 2005. Intentional action and intending: Recent empirical studies. Philosophical Psychology 18: 737–748.
Mele, A. 2006. The folk concept of intentional action: A commentary. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6: 277–290.
Mele, A., and F. Cushman. 2007. Intentional action, folk judgments, and stories: Sorting things out. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31: 184–201.
Myers-Schulz, B., and E. Schwitzgebel. 2013. Knowing that p without believing that p. Noûs.
Nadelhoffer, T. 2004a. On praise, side effects, and folk ascriptions of intentionality. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24: 196–213.
Nadelhoffer, T. 2004b. Blame, badness, and intentional action: A reply to Knobe and Mendlow. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24: 259–269.
Nadelhoffer, T. 2006. Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: Some problems for jury impartiality. Philosophical Explorations 9: 203–220.
Nichols, S., and J. Ulatowski. 2007. Intuitions and individual differences: The Knobe effect revisited. Mind & Language 22: 346–365.
Pettit, D., and J. Knobe. 2009. The pervasive impact of moral judgment. Mind & Language 24: 586–604.
Phelan, M. 2013. Evidence that stakes don’t matter to evidence. Philosophical Psychology
Phelan, M., and H. Sarkissian. 2008. The folk strike back: Or, why you didn’t do it intentionally, though it was bad and you knew it. Philosophical Studies 138: 291–298.
Rose, D., and J. Schaffer. 2013. Knowledge entails dispositional belief. Philosophical Studies.
Sverdlik, S. 2004. Intentionality and moral judgments in commonsense thought about action. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24: 224–236.
Tannenbaum, D., P. H. Ditto, and D. A. Pizarro. 2007. Different moral values produce different judgments of intentional action. Unpublished manuscript, University of California-Irvine.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Maria Capolupo, Sean Carey, Mattias Carosella, Phillip Collins, Danielle Curtin, Rachel Pazda, Jordan Pirdy, and Paul Poenicke who served as research assistants on this project. Thanks also to Mark Alfano, two anonymous reviewers at The Review of Philosophy and Psychology, and audience members at Eindhoven University of Technology and the 2012 meeting of the Society for Exact Philosophy for helpful comments on previous drafts of this paper.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Beebe, J.R. A Knobe Effect for Belief Ascriptions. Rev.Phil.Psych. 4, 235–258 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-013-0132-9
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-013-0132-9