Abstract
Quite a number of the philosophical arguments and objections currently being launched against simulation (ST) based and theory-theory (TT) based approaches to mindreading have a phenomenological heritage in that they draw on ideas found in the work of Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Stein, Gurwitsch, Scheler and Schutz. Within the last couple of years, a number of ST and TT proponents have started to react and respond to what one for the sake of simplicity might call the phenomenological proposal (PP). This paper addresses some of these critical responses, and distinguishes—in the process—substantive disagreements from terminological issues and other issues that are symptomatic of different research agendas. It does so by focusing specifically upon some objections made by Pierre Jacob. These epitomize the kinds of concerns that are being raised about PP at the moment, and thus facilitate a reply on behalf of PP that also applies more generally.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
Our respective accounts of empathy, for example, are quite different (cf. Gallagher 2011).
It is a slight irony that the example considered by Jacob was actually described by me as a case that more obviously exemplified sympathy than empathy (Zahavi 2008, 516). So in his attempt to show that the example involves a form of interpersonal similarity, Jacob is doing his best to undermine his own classification.
For the uninitiated, a trocar is a surgical instrument with a sharply pointed and often three-sided end which is used within a cannula, and designed to be inserted into a vein, artery, bone marrow or body cavity.
Just to avoid misunderstandings, when claiming that social perception is as direct as the perceptual experience of inanimate objects, the claim is not that interpersonal understanding ought to be modeled on our understanding of inanimate objects. The point is not that social perception is simply a subclass of object-perception. The claim is rather that it is a distinct form of intentionality that is as direct as object-perception.
In addition, one might also opt for a disjunctive account of behavior. As Overgaard puts it, “On this account, the difference between the person who genuinely vents her anger and the person feigning anger is not that in the former case, there is the angry behaviour plus a feeling of anger, while in the latter case, there is only the behaviour (or rather, that plus an intention to deceive, say). Rather, even if the two behaviours are movement-for-movement indistinguishable to an outside spectator, they are different kinds of processes. In the one case, the visible behaviour is a person’s coming to grips with the world as infuriating; in the other it is not” (Overgaard 2012).
That is also why I would object to a recent claim by Newen and Schlicht, namely that the central assertion of the Interaction-Theory defended by Gallagher and Zahavi is that in most cases—and this would include even complex mental states—we directly perceive what other people are up to (2010, 236). This is not my view. I am not denying that others can at times be very hard to figure out; I am denying that the very recognition of others as minded beings is a very challenging task, one that involves a leap from observable behavior to unobservable mental states.
It would at this point have been natural to consider and discuss Gallese’s notion of embodied simulation. This is so, not only because it seeks to offer a very basic and low-level account of action and emotion understanding that relies on mirror-resonance mechanisms, and because it has recently been subjected to an influential criticism by Jacob (2008), but also because Gallese explicitly and repeatedly claims that his own account is in line with, and a further development of, the account of interpersonal understanding found in Stein, Husserl and Merleau-Ponty (Gallese 2001, 2003, 2005). If this were correct, it would obviously challenge the suggestion that PP constitutes a real alternative to ST. However, since I am addressing this question in a separate publication, I will not pursue it further here (cf. Zahavi 2011).
Whereas it makes good sense to characterize different types of sub-personal information processing as simpler or more complex, it is harder to see an obvious application of the concept of “direct” in that domain, since all the processes will involve various degrees of mediation.
It is also intriguing that Jacob in presenting his own case writes that there is nearly universal consensus “that most, if not all, of another’s psychological states and experiences are unobservable” (Jacob 2011: § 1). Why this slight hesitation on his behalf? If he is prepared to accept that a few mental states might be observable, would he then also be prepared to accept that there might some cases where direct social perception is possible?
References
Avramides, A. 2001. Other minds. London: Routledge.
Bennett, M.R., and P.M.S. Hacker. 2003. Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.
Cassam, Q. 2007. The possibility of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Currie, G. 2008. Some ways to understand people. Philosophical Explorations 11: 211–218.
Davidson, D. 2001. Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
de Vignemont, F. 2010. Knowing other people’s mental states as it they were one’s own. In Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science, ed. D. Schmicking and S. Gallagher, 283–299. Dordrecht: Springer.
de Vignemont, F., and P. Jacob (2010/under review). What is it like to feel another’s pain?
de Vignemont, F., and T. Singer. 2006. The empathic brain: how, when and why? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10: 435–441.
Epley, N., and A. Waytz. 2009. Mind perception. In The handbook of social psychology, ed. S.T. Fiske, D.T. Gilbert, and G. Lindsay, 498–541. New York: Wiley.
Fuchs, T., and H. De Jaegher. 2009. Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(4): 465–486.
Gallagher, S. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. 2008. Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 535–543.
Gallagher, S. 2011. Empathy, simulation, and narrative. Science in context, in press.
Gallagher, S., and D. Zahavi. 2008. The phenomenological mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. New York: Routledge.
Gallese, V. 2001. The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 33–50.
Gallese, V. 2003. The manifold nature of interpersonal relations: the quest for a common mechanism. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society London, B 358: 517–528.
Gallese, V. 2005. Embodied simulation: From neurons to phenomenal experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4(1): 23–48.
Gallese, V., C. Keysers, and G. Rizzolatti. 2004. A unifying view of the basis of social cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8(9): 396–403.
Goldman, A.I. 1995. Interpretation psychologized. In Folk psychology: The theory of mind debate, ed. M. Davies and T. Stone, 74–99. Oxford: Blackwell.
Goldman, A.I. 2006. Simulating minds. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gurwitsch, A. 1979. Human encounters in the social world. Trans. F. Kersten. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Hatfield, E., R.L. Rapson, and Y.-C. Le. 2009. Emotional contagion and empathy. In The social neuroscience of empathy, ed. J. Decety and W. Ickes, 19–30. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Herschbach, M. 2008. Folk psychological and phenomenological accounts of social perception. Philosophical Explorations 11: 223–235.
Husserl, E. 1962. Phänomenologische psychologie. Husserliana 9. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
Husserl, E. 1999. Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology. Trans. D. Cairns. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Jacob, P. 2008. What do mirror neurons contribute to human social cognition? Mind and Language 23(2): 190–223.
Jacob, P. 2011. The direct-perception model of empathy: a critique. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. doi:10.1007/s13164-011-0065-0.
Jeannerod, M., and E. Pacherie. 2004. Agency, simulation, and self-identification. Mind and Language 19(2): 113–146.
Laird, J.D. 2007. Feelings: The perception of self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lipps, T. 1907. Das Wissen von fremden Ichen. Psychologische Untersuchungen 1: 694–722.
Malle, B.F. 2005. Three puzzles of mindreading. In Other minds: How humans bridge the divide between self and others, ed. B.F. Malle and S.D. Hodges, 26–43. New York: Guildford.
McCulloch, G. 2003. The life of the mind: An essay on phenomenological externalism. London: Routledge.
McNeill, W. E. S. 2011. On seeing that someone is angry. European Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1111/j.14680378.2010.00421.x.
Merleau-Ponty, M. 1963. The structure of behavior. Trans. A.L. Fisher. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. 1964. The primacy of perception. Trans. W. Cobb. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. 2002. Phenomenology of perception. Trans. C. Smith. London: Routledge.
Mitchell, J.P. 2008. Contributions of functional neuroimaging to the study of social cognition. Current Directions in Psychological Science 17(2): 142–146.
Newen, A., and T. Schlicht. 2009. Understanding other minds: A criticism of Goldman’s simulation theory and an outline of the person model theory. Grazer Philosophische Studien 79(1): 209–242.
Niedenthal, P.M. 2007. Embodying emotion. Science 316(5827): 1002–1005.
Onishi, K.H., and R. Baillargeon. 2005. Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science 308(5719): 255–258.
Overgaard, S. 2005. Rethinking other minds: Wittgenstein and Lévinas on expression. Inquiry 48(3): 249–274.
Overgaard, S. 2007. Wittgenstein and other minds: Rethinking subjectivity and intersubjectivity with Wittgenstein, Levinas, and Husserl. London: Routledge.
Overgaard, S. 2012. Other people. In Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology, ed. D. Zahavi. Oxford: Oxford University Press, in press.
Ratcliffe, M. 2007. Rethinking commonsense psychology. London: Palgrave MacMillan.
Rudd, A. 2003. Expressing the world: Skepticism, Wittgenstein, and Heidegger. Chicago: Open Court.
Scheler, M. 1954. The nature of sympathy. Trans. P. Heath. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Schutz, A. 1967. Phenomenology of the social world. Trans. G. Walsh & F. Lehnert. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Sinigaglia, C. 2008. Mirror neurons: This is the question. Journal of Consciousness Studies 15(10–11): 70–92.
Smith, J. 2010. Seeing other people. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXXI(3): 731–748.
Spaulding, S. 2010. Embodied cognition and mindreading. Mind & Language 25(1): 119–140.
Stich, S., and S. Nichols. 1995. Folk psychology: Simulation or tacit theory? In Folk psychology: The theory of mind debate, ed. M. Davies and T. Stone, 123–158. Oxford: Blackwell.
Stout, R. 2010. Seeing the anger in someone’s face. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 84: 29–43.
Thompson, E. 2001. Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 1–32.
Tomasello, M. 1999. The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Waldenfels, B. 1980. Der Spielraum des Verhaltens. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Zahavi, D. 1996. Husserl und die transzendentale Intersubjektivität. Eine Antwort auf die sprachpragmatische Kritik. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Zahavi, D. 2001. Beyond empathy. Phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 151–167.
Zahavi, D. 2002. Intersubjectivity in Sartre’s Being and nothingness. Alter 10: 265–281.
Zahavi, D. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Zahavi, D. 2007. Expression and empathy. In Folk psychology re-assessed, ed. D.D. Hutto and M. Ratcliffe, 25–40. Dordrecht: Springer.
Zahavi, D. 2008. Simulation, projection and empathy. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 514–522.
Zahavi, D. 2010. Empathy, embodiment and interpersonal understanding: From Lipps to Schutz. Inquiry 53(3): 285–306.
Zahavi, D. 2011. Empathy and mirroring: Husserl and Gallese. In Life, subjectivity and art. Essays in honor of Rudolf Bernet, eds. R. Breeur and U. Melle. Dordrecht: Springer, in press.
Zahavi, D., and S. Gallagher. 2008. The (in) visibility of others: a reply to Herschbach. Philosophical Explorations 11(3): 237–244.
Zahavi, D., and S. Overgaard. 2012. Empathy without isomorphism: A phenomenological account. In Empathy: from bench to bedside, ed. J. Decety. Cambridge: MIT Press. In press.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Galen Strawson, Pierre Jacob, Shaun Gallagher and an anonymous referee for helpful comments to an earlier version of this text.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Zahavi, D. Empathy and Direct Social Perception: A Phenomenological Proposal. Rev.Phil.Psych. 2, 541–558 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0070-3
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0070-3
Keywords
- Social Cognition
- Intentional Object
- Social Understanding
- Expressive Behavior
- Theoretical Inference