Skip to main content
Log in

Ontography and Maieutics, or Speculative Notes on an Ethos for Umwelt Theory

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is renewed interest in questions of ontology in various fields, as there has been in biosemiotics. But for umwelt theory, ontology needs to be approached in particular ways, in order to avoid it from being yet another “philosophy of access”, part and parcel of the epistemology-ontology dyad, where “ontology” is the leftover of epistemology, or any sort of subjective constitution of things. The article engages in philosophical considerations about what kinds of assumptions and preliminary considerations should be made for a semiosic ontology that was multiple, relational, and irreducible, with the principle goal being to engage with some terminological issues at the meeting point of ontology and umwelt theory. Ontography is proposed as a name for a low-key descriptive engagement with non-human umwelts considered as “worldings”, and maieutics as a particular attitude, or ethos, for the practical situation of direct inaccessibility of nonhuman umwelts. Parallels are drawn with the ontological turn in anthropology, which has also successfully engaged with alterity. A comparative study of umwelts should consider the ontological self-determination of the nonhuman other.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Ontology as the “study of what is” and meta-ontological commitment are purportedly different; yet since the entire truth of ontological claims is made dependent on claims of a theory, this distinction remains a paradigmatic example of a “philosophy of access” (Harman, 2005) where the entirety of an explanation remains on the side of “representation” (broadly construed), and can thus be considered irrelevant for present purposes.

  2. With a nod to all the sea urchins and others like them, whose legs move the animal and not the other way around, this transformation should probably be limited to creatures with a central nervous system, at least for the time being.

  3. Latour himself considers phenomenoloy to be last great dying gasp of the Modern Synthesis—a “tightrope walker doing the splits” (ibid.: 59)—but this need not concern us in this limited discussion. Umwelts are sets of relations, they are indeed “over the middle”—but with the corollary that since they are constitutive relations, the relata do not exist in the same shape and form independently of the relations as they do as part of the relations.

  4. For wonderful examples of an engagement with both the umwelt of animals and that of philosophers, see Kirksey 2015, Chap. 2 about ants, and Shaw et al., 2013 about mosquitoes.

References

  • Agamben, G. (2004). The Open: Man and Animal. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentley, A. F. (1941). The Human Skin: Philosophy’s Last Line of Defense. Philosophy of Science, 8, 1–19. https://doi.org/10.1086/286664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, A. E., & Segarra, M. (2011). Demenageries: Thinking (of) Animals after Derrida. Amsterdam New York: Rodopi

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J. (1980). About Looking. New York: Pantheon Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentari, C. (2015). Jakob von Uexküll: The Discovery of the Umwelt between Biosemiotics and Theoretical Biology. Dordrecht Heidelberg: Springer

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, B. (2008). Onto-Ethologies: The Animal Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze. Albany, NY: SUNY Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Calarco, M. (2011). Identity, Difference, Indistinction. CR: The New Centennial Review, 11(2), 41–60. https://doi.org/10.1353/ncr.2012.0008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrithers, M., Candea, M., Sykes, K., Holbraad, M., & Venkatesan, S. (2010). Ontology Is Just Another Word for Culture. Critique of Anthropology, 30, 152–200. https://doi.org/10.1177/0308275X09364070

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charbonnier, P., Salmon, G., & Skafish, P. (2016). Comparative Metaphysics: Ontology After Anthropology. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield International

    Google Scholar 

  • Cimatti, F. (2018). Bio-semiotic Ontology: The Philosophy of Giorgio Prodi. New York, NY: Springer Berlin Heidelberg

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, W. E. (2013). The ‘New Materialism’ and the Fragility of Things. Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 41(3), 399–412. https://doi.org/10.1177/0305829813486849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. M. (1902). Systematic Geography. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 41(170), 235–259

  • Deleuze, G. (1991). [1953]). Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature. New York: Columbia University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1994). What is philosophy?. New York: Columbia University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Descola, P. (2007). Beyond Nature and Culture. Proceedings of the British Academy, 139, 137–155. https://doi.org/10.5871/bacad/9780197263945.001.0001

  • Descola, P. (2013). Beyond Nature and Culture. Chicago; London: The University of Chicago Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Descola, P. (2014). Modes of being and forms of predication. Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory, 4(1), 271–280. https://doi.org/10.14318/hau4.1.012

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Favareau, D. (2015). Symbols are Grounded not in Things, but in Scaffolded Relations and their Semiotic Constraints (Or How the Referential Generality of Symbol Scaffolding Grows Minds). Biosemiotics, 8, 235–255. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-015-9234-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, C. (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Greif, M. (2015). The Age of the Crisis of Man. Thought and Fiction in America, 1933–1973. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (2005). Guerrilla Metaphysics: Phenomenology and the Carpentry of Things. Chicago: Open Court

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, N. (2012). [1923]). How Is Critical Ontology Possible? Toward the Foundation of the General Theory of the Categories, Part One. Axiomathes, 22, 315–354. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-012-9183-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendlin, Y. H. (in press). Object-Oriented Ontology and the Other of We in Anthropocentric Posthumanism

  • Herbrechter, S. (2018). Critical Posthumanism. In R. Braidotti, & M. Hlavajova (Eds.), Posthuman Glossary. London, New York: Bloomsbury Academic

    Google Scholar 

  • Holbraad, M. (2009). Ontography and Alterity: Defining Anthropological Truth. Social Analysis, 53(2), 80–93. https://doi.org/10.3167/sa.2009.530205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holbraad, M., & Pedersen, M. A. (2017). The Ontological Turn: An Anthropological Exposition. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kirksey, E. (2015). Emergent Ecologies. Durham: Duke University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kroeber, A. (1917). The Superorganic. American Anthropologist, 19(2), 163–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (2014). Zoosemiotics is the study of animal forms of knowing. Semiotica, 198, 47–60. https://doi.org/10.1515/sem-2013-0101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K., Emmeche, C., & Favareau, D. (2008). Biosemiotic Questions. Biosemiotics, 1, 41–55. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-008-9008-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1988). The Pasteurization of France. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1993). We Have Never Been Modern. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (2013). Ontography: Investigating the production of things, deflating ontology. Social Studies of Science, 43(3), 444–462. https://doi.org/10.1177/0306312713475925

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marchesini, R. (2017). Over the Human: Post-humanism and the Concept of Animal Epiphany. Cham, Switzerland: Springer

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meacham, D. (2016). How Low Can You Go? BioEnactivism, Cognitive Biology and Umwelt Ontology. Humana Mente Journal of Philosophical Studies, 31, 73–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What Is It Like to Be a Bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (2001). [1882]). The Gay Science. With a Prelude in German Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato, T. In: Complete Works, J. M. Cooper (Ed.), Indianapolis:Hackett

  • Pollner, M. (1987). Mundane Reason: Reality in Everyday and Sociological Discourse. Los Angeles: University of California

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1948). On What There Is. The Review of Metaphysics, 2(1), 21–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A. (2007). Ontological Commitment. Philosophy Compass, 2(3), 428–444. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2007.00080.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (2000). Essays on Life Itself. New York: Columbia University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, I. G. R., Jones, J. P., & Butterworth, M. K. (2013). The mosquito’s umwelt, or one monster’s standpoint ontology. Geoforum, 48, 260–267. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2012.11.028

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An Investigation on the Borderlines of Phenomenology, Ontology, and Semiotics. Dordrecht London: Springer

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viveiros de Castro, E. (1998). Cosmological Deixis and Amerindian Perspectivism. The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 4(3), 469–488. https://doi.org/10.2307/3034157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Viveiros, E. (2014). Cannibal Metaphysics: For a Post-structural Anthropology. Minneapolis: Univocal Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • de Viveiros, E. (2015a). The Relative Native: Essays on Indigenous Conceptual World. Chicago, IL: HAU Books

    Google Scholar 

  • de Viveiros, E. (2015b). Who Is Afraid of the Ontological Wolf? Some Comments on an Ongoing Anthropological Debate. The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology, 33(1), 2–17. https://doi.org/10.3167/ca.2015.330102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. (1926). Theoretical Biology. New York: Harcourt, Brace & Company, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. (2010). [1934]). A Foray into the Worlds of Animals and Humans with A Theory of Meaning. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (2015). [1920]). The Concept of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, C. (2010). What is Posthumanism?. Minneapolis, London: University of Minneapolis Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper was written with the support of the Estonian Research Council grant PRG314 “Semiotic fitting as a mechanism of biocultural diversity: instability and sustainability in novel environments”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Silver Rattasepp.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The author declares that there are no conflicts of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rattasepp, S. Ontography and Maieutics, or Speculative Notes on an Ethos for Umwelt Theory. Biosemiotics 15, 357–372 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-022-09492-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-022-09492-w

Keywords

Navigation