Neuroethics

, Volume 10, Issue 2, pp 319–323

Review of Nada Gligorov: Neuroethics and the Scientific Revision of Common Sense

Dordrecht: Springer, 2016. 169 pp. USD $99.99 (hardcover), $79.99 (ebook)
Brief Communication

Abstract

This ambitious book aims to make a substantive contribution to six separate debates within neuroethics — the existence of free will, the impact of cognitive enhancement and (separately) of memory management on personal identity, the nature of mental privacy, the supposed subjectivity of pain, and the proper definition of death — all in the context of a framing argument concerning the relation between common sense psychological concepts and scientific concepts. Gligorov means to rebut skepticism about folk mental states in the face of surprising neuroscientific results by reconceptualizing folk theories as protean, incorporating some of the very results that seem to challenge them. My impression is that Gligorov’s arguments on cognitive enhancement, memory modification, and brain death make helpful contributions to the respective literatures on those subjects, but I close with a number of concerns about the book, especially whether its framing argument is successful in its current form.

Keywords

Folk psychology Eliminativism Narrative identity Cognitive enhancement Death David Lewis 

References

  1. 1.
    Greene, Joshua, and Jonathan Cohen. 2004. For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 359(1451): 1775–1785.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Wegner, Daniel M. 2002. The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Libet, B., C.A. Gleason, E.W. Wright, and D.K. Pearl. 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain: A Journal of Neurology 106(Pt 3): 623–642.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Soon, Chun Siong, Marcel Brass, Hans-Jochen Heinze, and John-Dylan Haynes. 2008. Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nature Neuroscience 11(5): 543–545.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Frankfurt, Harry G. 1969. Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. The Journal of Philosophy 66 (23): 829–839.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Murray, Dylan, and Eddy Nahmias. 2014. Explaining away incompatibilist intuitions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88(2): 434–467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Liao, S. Matthew, and David T. Wasserman. 2007. Neuroethical concerns about moderating traumatic memories. American Journal of Bioethics 7(9): 38–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Liao, S. Matthew, and Anders Sandberg. 2008. The normativity of memory modification. Neuroethics 1(2): 85–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Loftus, Elizabeth F., and John C. Palmer. 1974. Reconstruction of automobile destruction an example of the interaction between language and memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 13: 585–589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Alexandre, Erler. 2011. Does memory modification threaten our authenticity? Neuroethics 4 (3): 235–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Bernat, J. L., C.M. Culver, and B. Gert. 1981. On the definition and criterion of death. Annals of Internal Medicine 94(3): 389–394.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Bernat, James L. 2006. The whole-brain concept of death remains optimum public policy. The Journal of Law Medicine & Ethics 34(1): 35–43.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Nada, Gligorov. 2016. A defense of brain death. Neuroethics 9(2): 119–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Fodor, J. A. 1974. Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese 28 (2): 97– 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. 15.
    Berthier, Marchcelo, Sergio Starkstein, and Ramon Leiguarda. 1988. Asymbolia for pain: A sensory-limbic disconnection syndrome. Annals of Neurology 24(1): 41–49.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Lewis, David. 1972. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50: 249–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. 17.
    Churchland, Paul M. 1989. A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of the mind and the structure of science. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Sellars, Wilfrid S. 1956. Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1: 253–329.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Lewis, David. 1970. How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy 67(13): 427–446. Reprinted in Lewis, David. 1983. Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Oxford University Press, New York, NY, pp. 78–95. References to this edition.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Jackson, Frank. 1998. From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.GRIN/CRÉUniversité de MontréalMontréalCanada

Personalised recommendations