Neuroethics

, Volume 9, Issue 3, pp 225–234 | Cite as

Moral Intuition or Moral Disengagement? Cognitive Science Weighs in on the Animal Ethics Debate

Original Paper

Abstract

In this paper I problematize the use of appeals to the common intuitions people have about the morality of our society’s current treatment of animals in order to defend that treatment. I do so by looking at recent findings in the field of cognitive science. First I will examine the role that appeals to common intuition play in philosophical arguments about the moral worth of animals, focusing on the work of Carl Cohen and Richard Posner. After describing the theory of Moral Disengagement—which has been used to explain how people live with themselves when they commit acts that they themselves believe are wrong—I will review the recent empirical research that details the nature of the moral disengagement that accompanies animal treatment. This includes studies that reveal that those who eat animals engage in the following behaviors: They minimize the nature of the harm of killing animals by casting the practice in a positive light; They obscure personal responsibility by blaming others for harms; They minimize the effect of the conduct on the animals by avoiding reference to the animal origins of meat; They derogate vegetarians as a way of avoiding feelings of guilt for their own practices. Perhaps most importantly, a number of empirical studies have shown that people’s intuitions about the moral worth of animals are shaped by their practice of eating animals—and not the other way around. In addition to the studies on moral disengagement, there is another body of research that has attempted to discover what accounts for the individual differences in attitudes people have toward the moral worth of animals. These studies have linked masculinity and traits like Authoritarianism, Social Dominance Orientation and Right Wing Authoritarianism to the tendency to disregard the moral worth of animals. I will briefly summarize this body of research and will then conclude by arguing that this data should cause us to be highly skeptical of the value that the common intuition that people who eat animals have about the moral status of animals may have in helping us understand the actual moral worth of animals.

Keywords

Animal ethics Cognitive science Animal rights Moral disengagement 

References

  1. 1.
    Graca, Joao, Maria Manuela Calheiros, and Abilio Oliveira. 2014. Moral disengagement in harmful but cherished food practices? An exploration into the case of meat. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 27: 749–765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Ruby, Matthew B. 2012. Vegetarianism. A blossoming field of study. Appetite 58: 141–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    Loughnan, Steve, Brock Bastian, and Nick Haslam. 2014. The psychology of eating animals. Directions in Psychological Science 23: 104–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Regan, Tom, and Peter Singer, eds. 1976. Animal rights and human obligations. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Clarke, Paul A.B., and Andrew Lindsey, eds. 1990. Political theory and animal rights. Winchester: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Garner, Robert. 2005. Animal ethics. Malden: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Taylor, Angus. 2003. Animals & ethics. Orchard Park: Broadview Press.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Frey, R.G. 1980. Interests and rights: The case against animals. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Carruthers, Peter. 1992. The animals issue: Moral theory in practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Regan, Tom. 1983. The case for animal rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Francione, Gary L. 2000. Introduction to animal rights: Your child or the dog? Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Singer, Peter. 1975. Animal liberation. New York: Avon Books.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Clark, Stephen R.L. 1977. The moral status of animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Carruthers, Peter. 1992. The animals issue: Moral theory in practice, 8–9. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. 15.
    Cohen, Carl, and Tom Regan. 2001. The animal rights debate, vol 31. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Posner, Richard. 2004. Animal rights: Legal, philosophical and pragmatic perspectives. In Animal Rights: Current debates and new directions, ed. Cass R Sunstein and Martha C. Nussbaum, 51–77. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Bandura, Albert. 1999. Moral disengagement in the perpetration of inhumanities. Personality and Social Psychology Review 3: 193–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Plous, Scott. 1993. Psychological mechanisms in the human use of animals. Journal of Social Issues 49: 11–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Schroder, Monika J.A., and Morven G. McEachern. 2004. Consumer value conflicts surrounding ethical food purchase decisions: A focus on animal welfare. International Journal of Consumer Studies 28: 168–177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Hoogland, Carolien T., Joop de Boer, and Jan J. Boersema. 2005. Transparency in the meat chain in the light of food culture and history. Appetite 45: 15–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Castano, Emanuele, and Roger Giner-Sorolla. 2006. Not quite human: Infrahumanization in response to collective responsibility for ingroup killing. Journal of Personal and Social Psychology 90: 804–818.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Cuddy, Amy J., Mindi S. Rock, and Michael I. Norton. 2007. Aid in the aftermath of Katrina: Inferences of secondary emotions and ingroup helping. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations 10: 107–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    Steve, Loughnan, Nick Haslam, and Brock Bastian. 2010. The role of meat consumption in the denial of mind and moral status to meat animals. Appetite 55(1): 156–9.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Bilewicz, Michal, Roland Imhoff, and Marek Drogosz. 2011. The humanity of what we eat: Conceptions of human uniqueness among vegetarians and omnivores. European Journal of Social Psychology 41: 201–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. 25.
    Bratanova, Boyka, Steve Loughnan, and Brock Bastian. 2011. The effect of categorization as food on the perceived moral standing of animals. Appetite 57: 193–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. 26.
    Bastian, Brock, Steve Loughnan, Nick Haslam, and H. Radke. 2012. Don’t mind meat? The denial of mind to animals used for human consumption. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 38: 247–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. 27.
    Minson, Julia A., and Benoit Monin. 2012. Do-gooder derogation: disparaging morally motivated minorities to defuse anticipated reproach. Social Psychological and Personality Science 3: 200–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 28.
    Rothgerber, Hank. 2014. Efforts to overcome vegetarian-induced dissonance among meat-eaters. Appetite 79: 32–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. 29.
    Fiddes, Nick. 1991. Meat: A natural symbol. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Adams, Carol. 1990. The sexual politics of meat: A feminist vegetarian critical theory. New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Ruby, Matthew B., and Steven J. Heine. 2011. Meat, morals, and masculinity. Appetite 56: 447–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. 32.
    Rothgerber, Hank. 2013. “Real men don’t eat (vegetable) quiche: Masculinity and the justification of meat consumption. The Psychology of Men and Masculinity 14: 363–375.Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Rozin, Paul, Julia M. Hormes, Myles S. Faith, and Brian Wansink. 2012. Is meat male? A quantitative multimethod framework to establish metaphoric relationships. Journal of Consumer Research 39: 629–643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. 34.
    Dhont, Krsitof, and Gordon Hodson. 2014. Why do right-wing adherents engage in more animal exploitation and meat consumption? Personality and Individual Differences 64: 12–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. 35.
    Allen, Michael, Mark Wilson, Sik Hung Ng, and Michael Dunne. 2000. Values and beliefs of vegetarians and omnivores. Journal of Social Psychology 140(4): 405–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 36.
    Allen, Michael W., and Sik Hung Ng. 2003. Human values, utilitarian benefits and identification: the case of meat. European Journal of Social Psychology 33: 37–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. 37.
    Chin, Matthew, Brian Fisak Jr., and Valerie Sims. 2002. Development of the attitudes toward vegetarians scale. Anthrozoös 15: 332–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Yale UniversityNew HavenUSA

Personalised recommendations