Neuroethics

, Volume 9, Issue 2, pp 147–157 | Cite as

Irrationality and Pathology of Beliefs

Original Paper

Abstract

Just as sadness is not always a symptom of mood disorder, irrational beliefs are not always symptoms of illness. Pathological irrational beliefs are distinguished from non-pathological ones by considering whether their existence is best explained by assuming some underlying dysfunctions. The features from which to infer the pathological nature of irrational beliefs are: un-understandability of their progression; uniqueness; coexistence with other psycho-physiological disturbances and/or concurrent decreased levels of functioning; bizarreness of content; preceding organic diseases known to be associated with irrational beliefs; treatment response to medical intervention, etc. Severe irrationality is sometimes caused by normal human motivation rather than by mental or physical dysfunction. Pure forms of self-deception may satisfy the diagnostic criteria of delusional disorder, but there may be no evidence that suggests that they are caused by illness. Although those with pathological delusions do not recognize their delusions as symptomatic of illness, differentiating pathological beliefs from normal irrational beliefs is vitally important: If a belief is pathological, psychiatrists must seriously consider treating the patient against her will. If it is not pathological, conversely, involuntary treatments are prohibited because they offend her basic autonomy.

Keywords

Delusion Distinction between normality and pathology Irrationality Self-deception 

References

  1. 1.
    Horwitz, Allan V., and Jerome C. Wakefield. 2007. The loss of sadness: How psychiatry transformed normal sorrow into depressive disorder. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Hohwy, Jakob, and Vivek Rajan. 2012. Delusions as forensically disturbing perceptual inferences. Neuroethics 5: 5–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    Currie, Gregory. 2000. Imagination, delusion and hallucinations. Mind and Language 15: 168–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Tumulty, Maura. 2012. Delusions and not-quite-beliefs. Neuroethics 5: 29–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Rosner, Richard, ed. 2000. Principles and practice of forensic psychiatry, 2nd ed. London: CRC Press.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    American Psychiatric Association. 2013. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, 5th ed. (DSM-5). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Publishing.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Jaspers, Karl. 1963. General psychopathology, trans. J. Hoenig and Marian W. Hamilton. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Fulford, K.W.M. 1989. Moral theory and medical practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Bortolotti, Lisa. 2010. Delusions and other irrational beliefs. Clarendon: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Cox, Daniel J., Linda Gonder-Frederick, Basim Antoun, Philip E. Cryer, and William L. Clarke. 1993. Perceived symptoms in the recognition of hypoglycemia. Diabetes Care 16: 519–527.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Lewis, Aubrey. 1934. The psychopathology of insight. British Journal of Medical Psychology 14: 332–348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    Bortolotti, Lisa. 2012. In defence of modest doxasticism about delusions. Neuroethics 5: 39–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. 13.
    Schneider, Kurt. 1959. Clinical psychopathology, trans. M. W. Hamilton. New York: Grune & Stratton.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    McKay, Ryan, and Lisa Cipolotti. 2007. Attributional style in a case of Cotard delusion. Consciousness and Cognition 16: 349–359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. 15.
    Young, Andrew W. 2000. Wondrous strange: the neuropsychology of abnormal beliefs. Mind and Language 15: 47–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Bleuler, Eugen. 1911. Dementia praecox oder Gruppe der Schizophrenien. Leipzig; Wien: Franz Deuticke.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Reznek, Lawrie. 1991. The philosophical defence of psychiatry. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Stitch, Stephen P. 1990. The fragmentation of reason: Preface to a pragmatic theory of cognitive evaluation. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Wakefield, Jerome C. 1992. The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist 47: 373–388.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Miyazono, Kengo. 2015. Delusions as harmful malfunctioning beliefs. Consciousness and Cognition 33: 561–573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Murphy, Dominic. 2013. Delusions, modernist epistemology and irrational belief. Mind and Language 28: 113–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Kapur, Shitij. 2003. Psychosis as a state of aberrant salience: A framework linking biology, phenomenology, and pharmacology in schizophrenia. American Journal of Psychiatry 160: 13–23.Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Maher, Brendan A. 1974. Delusional thinking and perceptual disorder. Journal of Individual Psychology 30: 98–113.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Cooper, Rachel. 2007. Psychiatry and philosophy of science. Stocksfield: Acumen.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Mukherjee, Sukdeb, Sashi Shukla, Joanne Woodle, Arnold M. Rosen, and Silvia Olarte. 1983. Misdiagnosis of schizophrenia in bipolar patients: a multiethnic comparison. American Journal of Psychiatry 140: 1571–1574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. 26.
    Sims, Andrew C.P. 2008. Sims' symptoms in the mind: An introduction to descriptive psychopathology, 4th ed. Edinburgh: Saunders.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Sims, Andrew C. 1992. Symptoms and beliefs. Journal of the Royal Society of Health 112: 42–46.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Cohen, Henry. 1955. The evolution of the concept of disease. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine 48: 155–160.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Kumral, Emre, and Ozgür Oztürk. 2004. Delusional state following acute stroke. Neurology 62: 110–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. 30.
    American Psychiatric Association. 2000. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, 4th ed., text revision (DSM-IV-TR). Washington, DC.: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Frith, C.D. 1987. The positive and negative symptoms of schizophrenia reflect impairments in the perception and initiation of action. Psychological Medicine 17: 631–648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. 32.
    Ramachandran, V.S. 1995. Anosognosia in parietal lobe syndrome. Consciousness and Cognition 4: 22–51.Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Coltheart, Max. 2007. The 33rd Sir Frederick Bartlett Lecture Cognitive neuropsychiatry and delusional belief. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 60: 1041–1062.Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Gipps, Richard G.T. 2010. The intelligibility of delusion. Current Opinion in Psychiatry 23: 556–560.Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    McKay, Ryan, Robyn Langdon, and Max Coltheart. 2007. Models of misbelief: Integrating motivational and deficit theories of delusions. Consciousness and Cognition 16: 932–941.Google Scholar
  36. 36.
    McKay, Ryan, Robyn Langdon, and Max Coltheart. 2005. “Sleights of mind”: Delusions, defences, and self-deception. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry 10: 305–326.Google Scholar
  37. 37.
    Jaspers, Karl. 1963. Eifersuchtswahn. Ein Beitrag zur Frage: “Entwicklung einer Persönlichkeit” oder “Prozeß”? In Gesammelte Schriften zur Psychopathologie, 85–190. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
  38. 38.
    Mele, Alfred R. 2001. Self-deception unmasked. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Buss, David M., and Martie Haselton. 2005. The evolution of jealousy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9: 506–507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. 40.
    Davies, Anne M. Aimola, Martin Davies, Jenni A. Ogden, Michael Smithson, and Rebekah C. White. 2009. Cognitive and motivational factors in anosognosia. In Delusions and self-deception: Affective and motivational influences on belief formation, eds. Tim Bayne and Jordi Fernández, 187–225. New York: Psychological Press.Google Scholar
  41. 41.
    Bortolotti, Lisa, and Matteo Memeli. 2012. Self-deception, delusion and the boundaries of folk psychology. Humanamente 20: 203–221.Google Scholar
  42. 42.
    Ramachandran, V.S. 1996. The evolutionary biology of self-deception, laughter, dreaming and depression: Some clues from anosognosia. Medical Hypotheses 47: 347–362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. 43.
    Mele, Alfred. 2009. Self-deception and delusions. In Delusion and self-deception: Affective and motivational influences on belief, eds. Tim Bayne and Jordi Fernández, 55–69. New York: Psychological Press.Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    Davies, Martin, and Max Coltheart. 2000. Introduction: pathologies of belief. Mind and Language 15: 1–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Graduate School of MedicineThe University of TokyoBunkyo-kuJapan

Personalised recommendations